Return to www.BrainFly.Net


THEAETETUS

by Plato

Translated by Benjamin Jowett (1817-1893)



INTRODUCTION AND ANALYSIS.

Some dialogues of Plato are of so various a character that their relation
to the other dialogues cannot be determined with any degree of certainty. 
The Theaetetus, like the Parmenides, has points of similarity both with his
earlier and his later writings.  The perfection of style, the humour, the
dramatic interest, the complexity of structure, the fertility of
illustration, the shifting of the points of view, are characteristic of his
best period of authorship.  The vain search, the negative conclusion, the
figure of the midwives, the constant profession of ignorance on the part of
Socrates, also bear the stamp of the early dialogues, in which the original
Socrates is not yet Platonized.  Had we no other indications, we should be
disposed to range the Theaetetus with the Apology and the Phaedrus, and
perhaps even with the Protagoras and the Laches.

But when we pass from the style to an examination of the subject, we trace
a connection with the later rather than with the earlier dialogues.  In the
first place there is the connexion, indicated by Plato himself at the end
of the dialogue, with the Sophist, to which in many respects the Theaetetus
is so little akin.  (1) The same persons reappear, including the younger
Socrates, whose name is just mentioned in the Theaetetus; (2) the theory of
rest, which Socrates has declined to consider, is resumed by the Eleatic
Stranger; (3) there is a similar allusion in both dialogues to the meeting
of Parmenides and Socrates (Theaet., Soph.); and (4) the inquiry into not-
being in the Sophist supplements the question of false opinion which is
raised in the Theaetetus.  (Compare also Theaet. and Soph. for parallel
turns of thought.)  Secondly, the later date of the dialogue is confirmed
by the absence of the doctrine of recollection and of any doctrine of ideas
except that which derives them from generalization and from reflection of
the mind upon itself.  The general character of the Theaetetus is
dialectical, and there are traces of the same Megarian influences which
appear in the Parmenides, and which later writers, in their matter of fact
way, have explained by the residence of Plato at Megara.  Socrates
disclaims the character of a professional eristic, and also, with a sort of
ironical admiration, expresses his inability to attain the Megarian
precision in the use of terms.  Yet he too employs a similar sophistical
skill in overturning every conceivable theory of knowledge.

The direct indications of a date amount to no more than this:  the
conversation is said to have taken place when Theaetetus was a youth, and
shortly before the death of Socrates.  At the time of his own death he is
supposed to be a full-grown man.  Allowing nine or ten years for the
interval between youth and manhood, the dialogue could not have been
written earlier than 390, when Plato was about thirty-nine years of age. 
No more definite date is indicated by the engagement in which Theaetetus is
said to have fallen or to have been wounded, and which may have taken place
any time during the Corinthian war, between the years 390-387.  The later
date which has been suggested, 369, when the Athenians and Lacedaemonians
disputed the Isthmus with Epaminondas, would make the age of Theaetetus at
his death forty-five or forty-six.  This a little impairs the beauty of
Socrates' remark, that 'he would be a great man if he lived.'

In this uncertainty about the place of the Theaetetus, it seemed better, as
in the case of the Republic, Timaeus, Critias, to retain the order in which
Plato himself has arranged this and the two companion dialogues.  We cannot
exclude the possibility which has been already noticed in reference to
other works of Plato, that the Theaetetus may not have been all written
continuously; or the probability that the Sophist and Politicus, which
differ greatly in style, were only appended after a long interval of time. 
The allusion to Parmenides compared with the Sophist, would probably imply
that the dialogue which is called by his name was already in existence;
unless, indeed, we suppose the passage in which the allusion occurs to have
been inserted afterwards.  Again, the Theaetetus may be connected with the
Gorgias, either dialogue from different points of view containing an
analysis of the real and apparent (Schleiermacher); and both may be brought
into relation with the Apology as illustrating the personal life of
Socrates.  The Philebus, too, may with equal reason be placed either after
or before what, in the language of Thrasyllus, may be called the Second
Platonic Trilogy.  Both the Parmenides and the Sophist, and still more the
Theaetetus, have points of affinity with the Cratylus, in which the
principles of rest and motion are again contrasted, and the Sophistical or
Protagorean theory of language is opposed to that which is attributed to
the disciple of Heracleitus, not to speak of lesser resemblances in thought
and language.  The Parmenides, again, has been thought by some to hold an
intermediate position between the Theaetetus and the Sophist; upon this
view, the Sophist may be regarded as the answer to the problems about One
and Being which have been raised in the Parmenides.  Any of these
arrangements may suggest new views to the student of Plato; none of them
can lay claim to an exclusive probability in its favour.

The Theaetetus is one of the narrated dialogues of Plato, and is the only
one which is supposed to have been written down.  In a short introductory
scene, Euclides and Terpsion are described as meeting before the door of
Euclides' house in Megara.  This may have been a spot familiar to Plato
(for Megara was within a walk of Athens), but no importance can be attached
to the accidental introduction of the founder of the Megarian philosophy. 
The real intention of the preface is to create an interest about the person
of Theaetetus, who has just been carried up from the army at Corinth in a
dying state.  The expectation of his death recalls the promise of his
youth, and especially the famous conversation which Socrates had with him
when he was quite young, a few days before his own trial and death, as we
are once more reminded at the end of the dialogue.  Yet we may observe that
Plato has himself forgotten this, when he represents Euclides as from time
to time coming to Athens and correcting the copy from Socrates' own mouth.
The narrative, having introduced Theaetetus, and having guaranteed the
authenticity of the dialogue (compare Symposium, Phaedo, Parmenides), is
then dropped.  No further use is made of the device.  As Plato himself
remarks, who in this as in some other minute points is imitated by Cicero
(De Amicitia), the interlocutory words are omitted.

Theaetetus, the hero of the battle of Corinth and of the dialogue, is a
disciple of Theodorus, the great geometrician, whose science is thus
indicated to be the propaedeutic to philosophy.  An interest has been
already excited about him by his approaching death, and now he is
introduced to us anew by the praises of his master Theodorus.  He is a
youthful Socrates, and exhibits the same contrast of the fair soul and the
ungainly face and frame, the Silenus mask and the god within, which are
described in the Symposium.  The picture which Theodorus gives of his
courage and patience and intelligence and modesty is verified in the course
of the dialogue.  His courage is shown by his behaviour in the battle, and
his other qualities shine forth as the argument proceeds.  Socrates takes
an evident delight in 'the wise Theaetetus,' who has more in him than 'many
bearded men'; he is quite inspired by his answers.  At first the youth is
lost in wonder, and is almost too modest to speak, but, encouraged by
Socrates, he rises to the occasion, and grows full of interest and
enthusiasm about the great question.  Like a youth, he has not finally made
up his mind, and is very ready to follow the lead of Socrates, and to enter
into each successive phase of the discussion which turns up.  His great
dialectical talent is shown in his power of drawing distinctions, and of
foreseeing the consequences of his own answers.  The enquiry about the
nature of knowledge is not new to him; long ago he has felt the 'pang of
philosophy,' and has experienced the youthful intoxication which is
depicted in the Philebus.  But he has hitherto been unable to make the
transition from mathematics to metaphysics.  He can form a general
conception of square and oblong numbers, but he is unable to attain a
similar expression of knowledge in the abstract.  Yet at length he begins
to recognize that there are universal conceptions of being, likeness,
sameness, number, which the mind contemplates in herself, and with the help
of Socrates is conducted from a theory of sense to a theory of ideas.

There is no reason to doubt that Theaetetus was a real person, whose name
survived in the next generation.  But neither can any importance be
attached to the notices of him in Suidas and Proclus, which are probably
based on the mention of him in Plato.  According to a confused statement in
Suidas, who mentions him twice over, first, as a pupil of Socrates, and
then of Plato, he is said to have written the first work on the Five
Solids.  But no early authority cites the work, the invention of which may
have been easily suggested by the division of roots, which Plato attributes
to him, and the allusion to the backward state of solid geometry in the
Republic.  At any rate, there is no occasion to recall him to life again
after the battle of Corinth, in order that we may allow time for the
completion of such a work (Muller).  We may also remark that such a
supposition entirely destroys the pathetic interest of the introduction.

Theodorus, the geometrician, had once been the friend and disciple of
Protagoras, but he is very reluctant to leave his retirement and defend his
old master.  He is too old to learn Socrates' game of question and answer,
and prefers the digressions to the main argument, because he finds them
easier to follow.  The mathematician, as Socrates says in the Republic, is
not capable of giving a reason in the same manner as the dialectician, and
Theodorus could not therefore have been appropriately introduced as the
chief respondent.  But he may be fairly appealed to, when the honour of his
master is at stake.  He is the 'guardian of his orphans,' although this is
a responsibility which he wishes to throw upon Callias, the friend and
patron of all Sophists, declaring that he himself had early 'run away' from
philosophy, and was absorbed in mathematics.  His extreme dislike to the
Heraclitean fanatics, which may be compared with the dislike of Theaetetus
to the materialists, and his ready acceptance of the noble words of
Socrates, are noticeable traits of character.

The Socrates of the Theaetetus is the same as the Socrates of the earlier
dialogues.  He is the invincible disputant, now advanced in years, of the
Protagoras and Symposium; he is still pursuing his divine mission, his
'Herculean labours,' of which he has described the origin in the Apology;
and he still hears the voice of his oracle, bidding him receive or not
receive the truant souls.  There he is supposed to have a mission to
convict men of self-conceit; in the Theaetetus he has assigned to him by
God the functions of a man-midwife, who delivers men of their thoughts, and
under this character he is present throughout the dialogue.  He is the true
prophet who has an insight into the natures of men, and can divine their
future; and he knows that sympathy is the secret power which unlocks their
thoughts.  The hit at Aristides, the son of Lysimachus, who was specially
committed to his charge in the Laches, may be remarked by the way.  The
attempt to discover the definition of knowledge is in accordance with the
character of Socrates as he is described in the Memorabilia, asking What is
justice? what is temperance? and the like.  But there is no reason to
suppose that he would have analyzed the nature of perception, or traced the
connexion of Protagoras and Heracleitus, or have raised the difficulty
respecting false opinion.  The humorous illustrations, as well as the
serious thoughts, run through the dialogue.  The snubnosedness of
Theaetetus, a characteristic which he shares with Socrates, and the man-
midwifery of Socrates, are not forgotten in the closing words.  At the end
of the dialogue, as in the Euthyphro, he is expecting to meet Meletus at
the porch of the king Archon; but with the same indifference to the result
which is everywhere displayed by him, he proposes that they shall
reassemble on the following day at the same spot.  The day comes, and in
the Sophist the three friends again meet, but no further allusion is made
to the trial, and the principal share in the argument is assigned, not to
Socrates, but to an Eleatic stranger; the youthful Theaetetus also plays a
different and less independent part.  And there is no allusion in the
Introduction to the second and third dialogues, which are afterwards
appended.  There seems, therefore, reason to think that there is a real
change, both in the characters and in the design.

The dialogue is an enquiry into the nature of knowledge, which is
interrupted by two digressions.  The first is the digression about the
midwives, which is also a leading thought or continuous image, like the
wave in the Republic, appearing and reappearing at intervals.  Again and
again we are reminded that the successive conceptions of knowledge are
extracted from Theaetetus, who in his turn truly declares that Socrates has
got a great deal more out of him than ever was in him.  Socrates is never
weary of working out the image in humorous details,--discerning the
symptoms of labour, carrying the child round the hearth, fearing that
Theaetetus will bite him, comparing his conceptions to wind-eggs, asserting
an hereditary right to the occupation.  There is also a serious side to the
image, which is an apt similitude of the Socratic theory of education
(compare Republic, Sophist), and accords with the ironical spirit in which
the wisest of men delights to speak of himself.

The other digression is the famous contrast of the lawyer and philosopher. 
This is a sort of landing-place or break in the middle of the dialogue.  At
the commencement of a great discussion, the reflection naturally arises,
How happy are they who, like the philosopher, have time for such
discussions (compare Republic)!  There is no reason for the introduction of
such a digression; nor is a reason always needed, any more than for the
introduction of an episode in a poem, or of a topic in conversation.  That
which is given by Socrates is quite sufficient, viz. that the philosopher
may talk and write as he pleases.  But though not very closely connected,
neither is the digression out of keeping with the rest of the dialogue. 
The philosopher naturally desires to pour forth the thoughts which are
always present to him, and to discourse of the higher life.  The idea of
knowledge, although hard to be defined, is realised in the life of
philosophy.  And the contrast is the favourite antithesis between the
world, in the various characters of sophist, lawyer, statesman, speaker,
and the philosopher,--between opinion and knowledge,--between the
conventional and the true.

The greater part of the dialogue is devoted to setting up and throwing down
definitions of science and knowledge.  Proceeding from the lower to the
higher by three stages, in which perception, opinion, reasoning are
successively examined, we first get rid of the confusion of the idea of
knowledge and specific kinds of knowledge,--a confusion which has been
already noticed in the Lysis, Laches, Meno, and other dialogues.  In the
infancy of logic, a form of thought has to be invented before the content
can be filled up.  We cannot define knowledge until the nature of
definition has been ascertained.  Having succeeded in making his meaning
plain, Socrates proceeds to analyze (1) the first definition which
Theaetetus proposes:  'Knowledge is sensible perception.'  This is speedily
identified with the Protagorean saying, 'Man is the measure of all things;'
and of this again the foundation is discovered in the perpetual flux of
Heracleitus.  The relativeness of sensation is then developed at length,
and for a moment the definition appears to be accepted.  But soon the
Protagorean thesis is pronounced to be suicidal; for the adversaries of
Protagoras are as good a measure as he is, and they deny his doctrine.  He
is then supposed to reply that the perception may be true at any given
instant.  But the reply is in the end shown to be inconsistent with the
Heraclitean foundation, on which the doctrine has been affirmed to rest. 
For if the Heraclitean flux is extended to every sort of change in every
instant of time, how can any thought or word be detained even for an
instant?  Sensible perception, like everything else, is tumbling to pieces.
Nor can Protagoras himself maintain that one man is as good as another in
his knowledge of the future; and 'the expedient,' if not 'the just and
true,' belongs to the sphere of the future.

And so we must ask again, What is knowledge?  The comparison of sensations
with one another implies a principle which is above sensation, and which
resides in the mind itself.  We are thus led to look for knowledge in a
higher sphere, and accordingly Theaetetus, when again interrogated, replies
(2) that 'knowledge is true opinion.'  But how is false opinion possible? 
The Megarian or Eristic spirit within us revives the question, which has
been already asked and indirectly answered in the Meno:  'How can a man be
ignorant of that which he knows?'  No answer is given to this not
unanswerable question.  The comparison of the mind to a block of wax, or to
a decoy of birds, is found wanting.

But are we not inverting the natural order in looking for opinion before we
have found knowledge?  And knowledge is not true opinion; for the Athenian
dicasts have true opinion but not knowledge.  What then is knowledge?  We
answer (3), 'True opinion, with definition or explanation.'  But all the
different ways in which this statement may be understood are set aside,
like the definitions of courage in the Laches, or of friendship in the
Lysis, or of temperance in the Charmides.  At length we arrive at the
conclusion, in which nothing is concluded.

There are two special difficulties which beset the student of the
Theaetetus:  (1) he is uncertain how far he can trust Plato's account of
the theory of Protagoras; and he is also uncertain (2) how far, and in what
parts of the dialogue, Plato is expressing his own opinion.  The dramatic
character of the work renders the answer to both these questions difficult.

1.  In reply to the first, we have only probabilities to offer.  Three main
points have to be decided:  (a) Would Protagoras have identified his own
thesis, 'Man is the measure of all things,' with the other, 'All knowledge
is sensible perception'?  (b) Would he have based the relativity of
knowledge on the Heraclitean flux?  (c) Would he have asserted the
absoluteness of sensation at each instant?  Of the work of Protagoras on
'Truth' we know nothing, with the exception of the two famous fragments,
which are cited in this dialogue, 'Man is the measure of all things,' and,
'Whether there are gods or not, I cannot tell.'  Nor have we any other
trustworthy evidence of the tenets of Protagoras, or of the sense in which
his words are used.  For later writers, including Aristotle in his
Metaphysics, have mixed up the Protagoras of Plato, as they have the
Socrates of Plato, with the real person.

Returning then to the Theaetetus, as the only possible source from which an
answer to these questions can be obtained, we may remark, that Plato had
'The Truth' of Protagoras before him, and frequently refers to the book. 
He seems to say expressly, that in this work the doctrine of the
Heraclitean flux was not to be found; 'he told the real truth' (not in the
book, which is so entitled, but) 'privately to his disciples,'--words which
imply that the connexion between the doctrines of Protagoras and
Heracleitus was not generally recognized in Greece, but was really
discovered or invented by Plato.  On the other hand, the doctrine that 'Man
is the measure of all things,' is expressly identified by Socrates with the
other statement, that 'What appears to each man is to him;' and a reference
is made to the books in which the statement occurs;--this Theaetetus, who
has 'often read the books,' is supposed to acknowledge (so Cratylus).  And
Protagoras, in the speech attributed to him, never says that he has been
misunderstood:  he rather seems to imply that the absoluteness of sensation
at each instant was to be found in his words.  He is only indignant at the
'reductio ad absurdum' devised by Socrates for his 'homo mensura,' which
Theodorus also considers to be 'really too bad.'

The question may be raised, how far Plato in the Theaetetus could have
misrepresented Protagoras without violating the laws of dramatic
probability.  Could he have pretended to cite from a well-known writing
what was not to be found there?  But such a shadowy enquiry is not worth
pursuing further.  We need only remember that in the criticism which
follows of the thesis of Protagoras, we are criticizing the Protagoras of
Plato, and not attempting to draw a precise line between his real
sentiments and those which Plato has attributed to him.

2.  The other difficulty is a more subtle, and also a more important one,
because bearing on the general character of the Platonic dialogues.  On a
first reading of them, we are apt to imagine that the truth is only spoken
by Socrates, who is never guilty of a fallacy himself, and is the great
detector of the errors and fallacies of others.  But this natural
presumption is disturbed by the discovery that the Sophists are sometimes
in the right and Socrates in the wrong.  Like the hero of a novel, he is
not to be supposed always to represent the sentiments of the author.  There
are few modern readers who do not side with Protagoras, rather than with
Socrates, in the dialogue which is called by his name.  The Cratylus
presents a similar difficulty:  in his etymologies, as in the number of the
State, we cannot tell how far Socrates is serious; for the Socratic irony
will not allow him to distinguish between his real and his assumed wisdom.
No one is the superior of the invincible Socrates in argument (except in
the first part of the Parmenides, where he is introduced as a youth); but
he is by no means supposed to be in possession of the whole truth. 
Arguments are often put into his mouth (compare Introduction to the
Gorgias) which must have seemed quite as untenable to Plato as to a modern
writer.  In this dialogue a great part of the answer of Protagoras is just
and sound; remarks are made by him on verbal criticism, and on the
importance of understanding an opponent's meaning, which are conceived in
the true spirit of philosophy.  And the distinction which he is supposed to
draw between Eristic and Dialectic, is really a criticism of Plato on
himself and his own criticism of Protagoras.

The difficulty seems to arise from not attending to the dramatic character
of the writings of Plato.  There are two, or more, sides to questions; and
these are parted among the different speakers.  Sometimes one view or
aspect of a question is made to predominate over the rest, as in the
Gorgias or Sophist; but in other dialogues truth is divided, as in the
Laches and Protagoras, and the interest of the piece consists in the
contrast of opinions.  The confusion caused by the irony of Socrates, who,
if he is true to his character, cannot say anything of his own knowledge,
is increased by the circumstance that in the Theaetetus and some other
dialogues he is occasionally playing both parts himself, and even charging
his own arguments with unfairness.  In the Theaetetus he is designedly held
back from arriving at a conclusion.  For we cannot suppose that Plato
conceived a definition of knowledge to be impossible.  But this is his
manner of approaching and surrounding a question.  The lights which he
throws on his subject are indirect, but they are not the less real for
that.  He has no intention of proving a thesis by a cut-and-dried argument;
nor does he imagine that a great philosophical problem can be tied up
within the limits of a definition.  If he has analyzed a proposition or
notion, even with the severity of an impossible logic, if half-truths have
been compared by him with other half-truths, if he has cleared up or
advanced popular ideas, or illustrated a new method, his aim has been
sufficiently accomplished.

The writings of Plato belong to an age in which the power of analysis had
outrun the means of knowledge; and through a spurious use of dialectic, the
distinctions which had been already 'won from the void and formless
infinite,' seemed to be rapidly returning to their original chaos.  The two
great speculative philosophies, which a century earlier had so deeply
impressed the mind of Hellas, were now degenerating into Eristic.  The
contemporaries of Plato and Socrates were vainly trying to find new
combinations of them, or to transfer them from the object to the subject. 
The Megarians, in their first attempts to attain a severer logic, were
making knowledge impossible (compare Theaet.).  They were asserting 'the
one good under many names,' and, like the Cynics, seem to have denied
predication, while the Cynics themselves were depriving virtue of all which
made virtue desirable in the eyes of Socrates and Plato.  And besides
these, we find mention in the later writings of Plato, especially in the
Theaetetus, Sophist, and Laws, of certain impenetrable godless persons, who
will not believe what they 'cannot hold in their hands'; and cannot be
approached in argument, because they cannot argue (Theat; Soph.).  No
school of Greek philosophers exactly answers to these persons, in whom
Plato may perhaps have blended some features of the Atomists with the
vulgar materialistic tendencies of mankind in general (compare Introduction
to the Sophist).

And not only was there a conflict of opinions, but the stage which the mind
had reached presented other difficulties hardly intelligible to us, who
live in a different cycle of human thought.  All times of mental progress
are times of confusion; we only see, or rather seem to see things clearly,
when they have been long fixed and defined.  In the age of Plato, the
limits of the world of imagination and of pure abstraction, of the old
world and the new, were not yet fixed.  The Greeks, in the fourth century
before Christ, had no words for 'subject' and 'object,' and no distinct
conception of them; yet they were always hovering about the question
involved in them.  The analysis of sense, and the analysis of thought, were
equally difficult to them; and hopelessly confused by the attempt to solve
them, not through an appeal to facts, but by the help of general theories
respecting the nature of the universe.

Plato, in his Theaetetus, gathers up the sceptical tendencies of his age,
and compares them.  But he does not seek to reconstruct out of them a
theory of knowledge.  The time at which such a theory could be framed had
not yet arrived.  For there was no measure of experience with which the
ideas swarming in men's minds could be compared; the meaning of the word
'science' could scarcely be explained to them, except from the mathematical
sciences, which alone offered the type of universality and certainty. 
Philosophy was becoming more and more vacant and abstract, and not only the
Platonic Ideas and the Eleatic Being, but all abstractions seemed to be at
variance with sense and at war with one another.

The want of the Greek mind in the fourth century before Christ was not
another theory of rest or motion, or Being or atoms, but rather a
philosophy which could free the mind from the power of abstractions and
alternatives, and show how far rest and how far motion, how far the
universal principle of Being and the multitudinous principle of atoms,
entered into the composition of the world; which could distinguish between
the true and false analogy, and allow the negative as well as the positive
a place in human thought.  To such a philosophy Plato, in the Theaetetus,
offers many contributions.  He has followed philosophy into the region of
mythology, and pointed out the similarities of opposing phases of thought. 
He has also shown that extreme abstractions are self-destructive, and,
indeed, hardly distinguishable from one another.  But his intention is not
to unravel the whole subject of knowledge, if this had been possible; and
several times in the course of the dialogue he rejects explanations of
knowledge which have germs of truth in them; as, for example, 'the
resolution of the compound into the simple;' or 'right opinion with a mark
of difference.'

...

Terpsion, who has come to Megara from the country, is described as having
looked in vain for Euclides in the Agora; the latter explains that he has
been down to the harbour, and on his way thither had met Theaetetus, who
was being carried up from the army to Athens.  He was scarcely alive, for
he had been badly wounded at the battle of Corinth, and had taken the
dysentery which prevailed in the camp.  The mention of his condition
suggests the reflection, 'What a loss he will be!'  'Yes, indeed,' replies
Euclid; 'only just now I was hearing of his noble conduct in the battle.' 
'That I should expect; but why did he not remain at Megara?'  'I wanted him
to remain, but he would not; so I went with him as far as Erineum; and as I
parted from him, I remembered that Socrates had seen him when he was a
youth, and had a remarkable conversation with him, not long before his own
death; and he then prophesied of him that he would be a great man if he
lived.'  'How true that has been; how like all that Socrates said!  And
could you repeat the conversation?'  'Not from memory; but I took notes
when I returned home, which I afterwards filled up at leisure, and got
Socrates to correct them from time to time, when I came to
Athens'...Terpsion had long intended to ask for a sight of this writing, of
which he had already heard.  They are both tired, and agree to rest and
have the conversation read to them by a servant...'Here is the roll,
Terpsion; I need only observe that I have omitted, for the sake of
convenience, the interlocutory words, "said I," "said he"; and that
Theaetetus, and Theodorus, the geometrician of Cyrene, are the persons with
whom Socrates is conversing.'

Socrates begins by asking Theodorus whether, in his visit to Athens, he has
found any Athenian youth likely to attain distinction in science.  'Yes,
Socrates, there is one very remarkable youth, with whom I have become
acquainted.  He is no beauty, and therefore you need not imagine that I am
in love with him; and, to say the truth, he is very like you, for he has a
snub nose, and projecting eyes, although these features are not so marked
in him as in you.  He combines the most various qualities, quickness,
patience, courage; and he is gentle as well as wise, always silently
flowing on, like a river of oil.  Look! he is the middle one of those who
are entering the palaestra.'

Socrates, who does not know his name, recognizes him as the son of
Euphronius, who was himself a good man and a rich.  He is informed by
Theodorus that the youth is named Theaetetus, but the property of his
father has disappeared in the hands of trustees; this does not, however,
prevent him from adding liberality to his other virtues.  At the desire of
Socrates he invites Theaetetus to sit by them.

'Yes,' says Socrates, 'that I may see in you, Theaetetus, the image of my
ugly self, as Theodorus declares.  Not that his remark is of any
importance; for though he is a philosopher, he is not a painter, and
therefore he is no judge of our faces; but, as he is a man of science, he
may be a judge of our intellects.  And if he were to praise the mental
endowments of either of us, in that case the hearer of the eulogy ought to
examine into what he says, and the subject should not refuse to be
examined.'  Theaetetus consents, and is caught in a trap (compare the
similar trap which is laid for Theodorus).  'Then, Theaetetus, you will
have to be examined, for Theodorus has been praising you in a style of
which I never heard the like.'  'He was only jesting.'  'Nay, that is not
his way; and I cannot allow you, on that pretence, to retract the assent
which you have already given, or I shall make Theodorus repeat your
praises, and swear to them.'  Theaetetus, in reply, professes that he is
willing to be examined, and Socrates begins by asking him what he learns of
Theodorus.  He is himself anxious to learn anything of anybody; and now he
has a little question to which he wants Theaetetus or Theodorus (or
whichever of the company would not be 'donkey' to the rest) to find an
answer.  Without further preface, but at the same time apologizing for his
eagerness, he asks, 'What is knowledge?'  Theodorus is too old to answer
questions, and begs him to interrogate Theaetetus, who has the advantage of
youth.

Theaetetus replies, that knowledge is what he learns of Theodorus, i.e.
geometry and arithmetic; and that there are other kinds of knowledge--
shoemaking, carpentering, and the like.  But Socrates rejoins, that this
answer contains too much and also too little.  For although Theaetetus has
enumerated several kinds of knowledge, he has not explained the common
nature of them; as if he had been asked, 'What is clay?' and instead of
saying 'Clay is moistened earth,' he had answered, 'There is one clay of
image-makers, another of potters, another of oven-makers.'  Theaetetus at
once divines that Socrates means him to extend to all kinds of knowledge
the same process of generalization which he has already learned to apply to
arithmetic.  For he has discovered a division of numbers into square
numbers, 4, 9, 16, etc., which are composed of equal factors, and represent
figures which have equal sides, and oblong numbers, 3, 5, 6, 7, etc., which
are composed of unequal factors, and represent figures which have unequal
sides.  But he has never succeeded in attaining a similar conception of
knowledge, though he has often tried; and, when this and similar questions
were brought to him from Socrates, has been sorely distressed by them. 
Socrates explains to him that he is in labour.  For men as well as women
have pangs of labour; and both at times require the assistance of midwives. 
And he, Socrates, is a midwife, although this is a secret; he has inherited
the art from his mother bold and bluff, and he ushers into light, not
children, but the thoughts of men.  Like the midwives, who are 'past
bearing children,' he too can have no offspring--the God will not allow him
to bring anything into the world of his own.  He also reminds Theaetetus
that the midwives are or ought to be the only matchmakers (this is the
preparation for a biting jest); for those who reap the fruit are most
likely to know on what soil the plants will grow.  But respectable midwives
avoid this department of practice--they do not want to be called
procuresses.  There are some other differences between the two sorts of
pregnancy.  For women do not bring into the world at one time real children
and at another time idols which are with difficulty distinguished from
them.  'At first,' says Socrates in his character of the man-midwife, 'my
patients are barren and stolid, but after a while they "round apace," if
the gods are propitious to them; and this is due not to me but to
themselves; I and the god only assist in bringing their ideas to the birth. 
Many of them have left me too soon, and the result has been that they have
produced abortions; or when I have delivered them of children they have
lost them by an ill bringing up, and have ended by seeing themselves, as
others see them, to be great fools.  Aristides, the son of Lysimachus, is
one of these, and there have been others.  The truants often return to me
and beg to be taken back; and then, if my familiar allows me, which is not
always the case, I receive them, and they begin to grow again.  There come
to me also those who have nothing in them, and have no need of my art; and
I am their matchmaker (see above), and marry them to Prodicus or some other
inspired sage who is likely to suit them.  I tell you this long story
because I suspect that you are in labour.  Come then to me, who am a
midwife, and the son of a midwife, and I will deliver you.  And do not bite
me, as the women do, if I abstract your first-born; for I am acting out of
good-will towards you; the God who is within me is the friend of man,
though he will not allow me to dissemble the truth.  Once more then,
Theaetetus, I repeat my old question--"What is knowledge?"  Take courage,
and by the help of God you will discover an answer.'  'My answer is, that
knowledge is perception.'  'That is the theory of Protagoras, who has
another way of expressing the same thing when he says, "Man is the measure
of all things."  He was a very wise man, and we should try to understand
him.  In order to illustrate his meaning let me suppose that there is the
same wind blowing in our faces, and one of us may be hot and the other
cold.  How is this?  Protagoras will reply that the wind is hot to him who
is cold, cold to him who is hot.  And "is" means "appears," and when you
say "appears to him," that means "he feels."  Thus feeling, appearance,
perception, coincide with being.  I suspect, however, that this was only a
"facon de parler," by which he imposed on the common herd like you and me;
he told "the truth" (in allusion to the title of his book, which was called
"The Truth") in secret to his disciples.  For he was really a votary of
that famous philosophy in which all things are said to be relative; nothing
is great or small, or heavy or light, or one, but all is in motion and
mixture and transition and flux and generation, not "being," as we
ignorantly affirm, but "becoming."  This has been the doctrine, not of
Protagoras only, but of all philosophers, with the single exception of
Parmenides; Empedocles, Heracleitus, and others, and all the poets, with
Epicharmus, the king of Comedy, and Homer, the king of Tragedy, at their
head, have said the same; the latter has these words--

"Ocean, whence the gods sprang, and mother Tethys."

And many arguments are used to show, that motion is the source of life, and
rest of death:  fire and warmth are produced by friction, and living
creatures owe their origin to a similar cause; the bodily frame is
preserved by exercise and destroyed by indolence; and if the sun ceased to
move, "chaos would come again."  Now apply this doctrine of "All is motion"
to the senses, and first of all to the sense of sight.  The colour of
white, or any other colour, is neither in the eyes nor out of them, but
ever in motion between the object and the eye, and varying in the case of
every percipient.  All is relative, and, as the followers of Protagoras
remark, endless contradictions arise when we deny this; e.g. here are six
dice; they are more than four and less than twelve; "more and also less,"
would you not say?'  'Yes.'  'But Protagoras will retort:  "Can anything be
more or less without addition or subtraction?"'

'I should say "No" if I were not afraid of contradicting my former answer.'

'And if you say "Yes," the tongue will escape conviction but not the mind,
as Euripides would say?'  'True.'  'The thoroughbred Sophists, who know all
that can be known, would have a sparring match over this, but you and I,
who have no professional pride, want only to discover whether our ideas are
clear and consistent.  And we cannot be wrong in saying, first, that
nothing can be greater or less while remaining equal; secondly, that there
can be no becoming greater or less without addition or subtraction;
thirdly, that what is and was not, cannot be without having become.  But
then how is this reconcilable with the case of the dice, and with similar
examples?--that is the question.'  'I am often perplexed and amazed,
Socrates, by these difficulties.'  'That is because you are a philosopher,
for philosophy begins in wonder, and Iris is the child of Thaumas.  Do you
know the original principle on which the doctrine of Protagoras is based?' 
'No.'  'Then I will tell you; but we must not let the uninitiated hear, and
by the uninitiated I mean the obstinate people who believe in nothing which
they cannot hold in their hands.  The brethren whose mysteries I am about
to unfold to you are far more ingenious.  They maintain that all is motion;
and that motion has two forms, action and passion, out of which endless
phenomena are created, also in two forms--sense and the object of sense--
which come to the birth together.  There are two kinds of motions, a slow
and a fast; the motions of the agent and the patient are slower, because
they move and create in and about themselves, but the things which are born
of them have a swifter motion, and pass rapidly from place to place.  The
eye and the appropriate object come together, and give birth to whiteness
and the sensation of whiteness; the eye is filled with seeing, and becomes
not sight but a seeing eye, and the object is filled with whiteness, and
becomes not whiteness but white; and no other compound of either with
another would have produced the same effect.  All sensation is to be
resolved into a similar combination of an agent and patient.  Of either,
taken separately, no idea can be formed; and the agent may become a
patient, and the patient an agent.  Hence there arises a general reflection
that nothing is, but all things become; no name can detain or fix them. 
Are not these speculations charming, Theaetetus, and very good for a person
in your interesting situation?  I am offering you specimens of other men's
wisdom, because I have no wisdom of my own, and I want to deliver you of
something; and presently we will see whether you have brought forth wind or
not.  Tell me, then, what do you think of the notion that "All things are
becoming"?'

'When I hear your arguments, I am marvellously ready to assent.'

'But I ought not to conceal from you that there is a serious objection
which may be urged against this doctrine of Protagoras.  For there are
states, such as madness and dreaming, in which perception is false; and
half our life is spent in dreaming; and who can say that at this instant we
are not dreaming?  Even the fancies of madmen are real at the time.  But if
knowledge is perception, how can we distinguish between the true and the
false in such cases?  Having stated the objection, I will now state the
answer.  Protagoras would deny the continuity of phenomena; he would say
that what is different is entirely different, and whether active or passive
has a different power.  There are infinite agents and patients in the
world, and these produce in every combination of them a different
perception.  Take myself as an instance:--Socrates may be ill or he may be
well,--and remember that Socrates, with all his accidents, is spoken of. 
The wine which I drink when I am well is pleasant to me, but the same wine
is unpleasant to me when I am ill.  And there is nothing else from which I
can receive the same impression, nor can another receive the same
impression from the wine.  Neither can I and the object of sense become
separately what we become together.  For the one in becoming is relative to
the other, but they have no other relation; and the combination of them is
absolute at each moment.  (In modern language, the act of sensation is
really indivisible, though capable of a mental analysis into subject and
object.)  My sensation alone is true, and true to me only.  And therefore,
as Protagoras says, "To myself I am the judge of what is and what is not." 
Thus the flux of Homer and Heracleitus, the great Protagorean saying that
"Man is the measure of all things," the doctrine of Theaetetus that
"Knowledge is perception," have all the same meaning.  And this is thy new-
born child, which by my art I have brought to light; and you must not be
angry if instead of rearing your infant we expose him.'

'Theaetetus will not be angry,' says Theodorus; 'he is very good-natured. 
But I should like to know, Socrates, whether you mean to say that all this
is untrue?'

'First reminding you that I am not the bag which contains the arguments,
but that I extract them from Theaetetus, shall I tell you what amazes me in
your friend Protagoras?'

'What may that be?'

'I like his doctrine that what appears is; but I wonder that he did not
begin his great work on Truth with a declaration that a pig, or a dog-faced
baboon, or any other monster which has sensation, is a measure of all
things; then, while we were reverencing him as a god, he might have
produced a magnificent effect by expounding to us that he was no wiser than
a tadpole.  For if sensations are always true, and one man's discernment is
as good as another's, and every man is his own judge, and everything that
he judges is right and true, then what need of Protagoras to be our
instructor at a high figure; and why should we be less knowing than he is,
or have to go to him, if every man is the measure of all things?  My own
art of midwifery, and all dialectic, is an enormous folly, if Protagoras'
"Truth" be indeed truth, and the philosopher is not merely amusing himself
by giving oracles out of his book.'

Theodorus thinks that Socrates is unjust to his master, Protagoras; but he
is too old and stiff to try a fall with him, and therefore refers him to
Theaetetus, who is already driven out of his former opinion by the
arguments of Socrates.

Socrates then takes up the defence of Protagoras, who is supposed to reply
in his own person--'Good people, you sit and declaim about the gods, of
whose existence or non-existence I have nothing to say, or you discourse
about man being reduced to the level of the brutes; but what proof have you
of your statements?  And yet surely you and Theodorus had better reflect
whether probability is a safe guide.  Theodorus would be a bad geometrician
if he had nothing better to offer.'...Theaetetus is affected by the appeal
to geometry, and Socrates is induced by him to put the question in a new
form.  He proceeds as follows:--'Should we say that we know what we see and
hear,--e.g. the sound of words or the sight of letters in a foreign
tongue?'

'We should say that the figures of the letters, and the pitch of the voice
in uttering them, were known to us, but not the meaning of them.'

'Excellent; I want you to grow, and therefore I will leave that answer and
ask another question:  Is not seeing perceiving?'  'Very true.'  'And he
who sees knows?'  'Yes.'  'And he who remembers, remembers that which he
sees and knows?'  'Very true.'  'But if he closes his eyes, does he not
remember?'  'He does.'  'Then he may remember and not see; and if seeing is
knowing, he may remember and not know.  Is not this a "reductio ad
absurdum" of the hypothesis that knowledge is sensible perception?  Yet
perhaps we are crowing too soon; and if Protagoras, "the father of the
myth," had been alive, the result might have been very different.  But he
is dead, and Theodorus, whom he left guardian of his "orphan," has not been
very zealous in defending him.'

Theodorus objects that Callias is the true guardian, but he hopes that
Socrates will come to the rescue.  Socrates prefaces his defence by
resuming the attack.  He asks whether a man can know and not know at the
same time?  'Impossible.'  Quite possible, if you maintain that seeing is
knowing.  The confident adversary, suiting the action to the word, shuts
one of your eyes; and now, says he, you see and do not see, but do you know
and not know?  And a fresh opponent darts from his ambush, and transfers to
knowledge the terms which are commonly applied to sight.  He asks whether
you can know near and not at a distance; whether you can have a sharp and
also a dull knowledge.  While you are wondering at his incomparable wisdom,
he gets you into his power, and you will not escape until you have come to
an understanding with him about the money which is to be paid for your
release.

But Protagoras has not yet made his defence; and already he may be heard
contemptuously replying that he is not responsible for the admissions which
were made by a boy, who could not foresee the coming move, and therefore
had answered in a manner which enabled Socrates to raise a laugh against
himself.  'But I cannot be fairly charged,' he will say, 'with an answer
which I should not have given; for I never maintained that the memory of a
feeling is the same as a feeling, or denied that a man might know and not
know the same thing at the same time.  Or, if you will have extreme
precision, I say that man in different relations is many or rather infinite
in number.  And I challenge you, either to show that his perceptions are
not individual, or that if they are, what appears to him is not what is. 
As to your pigs and baboons, you are yourself a pig, and you make my
writings a sport of other swine.  But I still affirm that man is the
measure of all things, although I admit that one man may be a thousand
times better than another, in proportion as he has better impressions. 
Neither do I deny the existence of wisdom or of the wise man.  But I
maintain that wisdom is a practical remedial power of turning evil into
good, the bitterness of disease into the sweetness of health, and does not
consist in any greater truth or superior knowledge.  For the impressions of
the sick are as true as the impressions of the healthy; and the sick are as
wise as the healthy.  Nor can any man be cured of a false opinion, for
there is no such thing; but he may be cured of the evil habit which
generates in him an evil opinion.  This is effected in the body by the
drugs of the physician, and in the soul by the words of the Sophist; and
the new state or opinion is not truer, but only better than the old.  And
philosophers are not tadpoles, but physicians and husbandmen, who till the
soil and infuse health into animals and plants, and make the good take the
place of the evil, both in individuals and states.  Wise and good
rhetoricians make the good to appear just in states (for that is just which
appears just to a state), and in return, they deserve to be well paid.  And
you, Socrates, whether you please or not, must continue to be a measure. 
This is my defence, and I must request you to meet me fairly.  We are
professing to reason, and not merely to dispute; and there is a great
difference between reasoning and disputation.  For the disputer is always
seeking to trip up his opponent; and this is a mode of argument which
disgusts men with philosophy as they grow older.  But the reasoner is
trying to understand him and to point out his errors to him, whether
arising from his own or from his companion's fault; he does not argue from
the customary use of names, which the vulgar pervert in all manner of ways. 
If you are gentle to an adversary he will follow and love you; and if
defeated he will lay the blame on himself, and seek to escape from his own
prejudices into philosophy.  I would recommend you, Socrates, to adopt this
humaner method, and to avoid captious and verbal criticisms.'

Such, Theodorus, is the very slight help which I am able to afford to your
friend; had he been alive, he would have helped himself in far better
style.

'You have made a most valorous defence.'

Yes; but did you observe that Protagoras bade me be serious, and complained
of our getting up a laugh against him with the aid of a boy?  He meant to
intimate that you must take the place of Theaetetus, who may be wiser than
many bearded men, but not wiser than you, Theodorus.

'The rule of the Spartan Palaestra is, Strip or depart; but you are like
the giant Antaeus, and will not let me depart unless I try a fall with
you.'

Yes, that is the nature of my complaint.  And many a Hercules, many a
Theseus mighty in deeds and words has broken my head; but I am always at
this rough game.  Please, then, to favour me.

'On the condition of not exceeding a single fall, I consent.'

Socrates now resumes the argument.  As he is very desirous of doing justice
to Protagoras, he insists on citing his own words,--'What appears to each
man is to him.'  And how, asks Socrates, are these words reconcileable with
the fact that all mankind are agreed in thinking themselves wiser than
others in some respects, and inferior to them in others?  In the hour of
danger they are ready to fall down and worship any one who is their
superior in wisdom as if he were a god.  And the world is full of men who
are asking to be taught and willing to be ruled, and of other men who are
willing to rule and teach them.  All which implies that men do judge of one
another's impressions, and think some wise and others foolish.  How will
Protagoras answer this argument?  For he cannot say that no one deems
another ignorant or mistaken.  If you form a judgment, thousands and tens
of thousands are ready to maintain the opposite.  The multitude may not and
do not agree in Protagoras' own thesis that 'Man is the measure of all
things;' and then who is to decide?  Upon his own showing must not his
'truth' depend on the number of suffrages, and be more or less true in
proportion as he has more or fewer of them?  And he must acknowledge
further, that they speak truly who deny him to speak truly, which is a
famous jest.  And if he admits that they speak truly who deny him to speak
truly, he must admit that he himself does not speak truly.  But his
opponents will refuse to admit this of themselves, and he must allow that
they are right in their refusal.  The conclusion is, that all mankind,
including Protagoras himself, will deny that he speaks truly; and his truth
will be true neither to himself nor to anybody else.

Theodorus is inclined to think that this is going too far.  Socrates
ironically replies, that he is not going beyond the truth.  But if the old
Protagoras could only pop his head out of the world below, he would
doubtless give them both a sound castigation and be off to the shades in an
instant.  Seeing that he is not within call, we must examine the question
for ourselves.  It is clear that there are great differences in the
understandings of men.  Admitting, with Protagoras, that immediate
sensations of hot, cold, and the like, are to each one such as they appear,
yet this hypothesis cannot be extended to judgments or opinions.  And even
if we were to admit further,--and this is the view of some who are not
thorough-going followers of Protagoras,--that right and wrong, holy and
unholy, are to each state or individual such as they appear, still
Protagoras will not venture to maintain that every man is equally the
measure of expediency, or that the thing which seems is expedient to every
one.  But this begins a new question.  'Well, Socrates, we have plenty of
leisure.  Yes, we have, and, after the manner of philosophers, we are
digressing; I have often observed how ridiculous this habit of theirs makes
them when they appear in court.  'What do you mean?'  I mean to say that a
philosopher is a gentleman, but a lawyer is a servant.  The one can have
his talk out, and wander at will from one subject to another, as the fancy
takes him; like ourselves, he may be long or short, as he pleases.  But the
lawyer is always in a hurry; there is the clepsydra limiting his time, and
the brief limiting his topics, and his adversary is standing over him and
exacting his rights.  He is a servant disputing about a fellow-servant
before his master, who holds the cause in his hands; the path never
diverges, and often the race is for his life.  Such experiences render him
keen and shrewd; he learns the arts of flattery, and is perfect in the
practice of crooked ways; dangers have come upon him too soon, when the
tenderness of youth was unable to meet them with truth and honesty, and he
has resorted to counter-acts of dishonesty and falsehood, and become warped
and distorted; without any health or freedom or sincerity in him he has
grown up to manhood, and is or esteems himself to be a master of cunning. 
Such are the lawyers; will you have the companion picture of philosophers?
or will this be too much of a digression?

'Nay, Socrates, the argument is our servant, and not our master.  Who is
the judge or where is the spectator, having a right to control us?'

I will describe the leaders, then:  for the inferior sort are not worth the
trouble.  The lords of philosophy have not learned the way to the dicastery
or ecclesia; they neither see nor hear the laws and votes of the state,
written or recited; societies, whether political or festive, clubs, and
singing maidens do not enter even into their dreams.  And the scandals of
persons or their ancestors, male and female, they know no more than they
can tell the number of pints in the ocean.  Neither are they conscious of
their own ignorance; for they do not practise singularity in order to gain
reputation, but the truth is, that the outer form of them only is residing
in the city; the inner man, as Pindar says, is going on a voyage of
discovery, measuring as with line and rule the things which are under and
in the earth, interrogating the whole of nature, only not condescending to
notice what is near them.

'What do you mean, Socrates?'

I will illustrate my meaning by the jest of the witty maid-servant, who saw
Thales tumbling into a well, and said of him, that he was so eager to know
what was going on in heaven, that he could not see what was before his
feet.  This is applicable to all philosophers.  The philosopher is
unacquainted with the world; he hardly knows whether his neighbour is a man
or an animal.  For he is always searching into the essence of man, and
enquiring what such a nature ought to do or suffer different from any
other.  Hence, on every occasion in private life and public, as I was
saying, when he appears in a law-court or anywhere, he is the joke, not
only of maid-servants, but of the general herd, falling into wells and
every sort of disaster; he looks such an awkward, inexperienced creature,
unable to say anything personal, when he is abused, in answer to his
adversaries (for he knows no evil of any one); and when he hears the
praises of others, he cannot help laughing from the bottom of his soul at
their pretensions; and this also gives him a ridiculous appearance.  A king
or tyrant appears to him to be a kind of swine-herd or cow-herd, milking
away at an animal who is much more troublesome and dangerous than cows or
sheep; like the cow-herd, he has no time to be educated, and the pen in
which he keeps his flock in the mountains is surrounded by a wall.  When he
hears of large landed properties of ten thousand acres or more, he thinks
of the whole earth; or if he is told of the antiquity of a family, he
remembers that every one has had myriads of progenitors, rich and poor,
Greeks and barbarians, kings and slaves.  And he who boasts of his descent
from Amphitryon in the twenty-fifth generation, may, if he pleases, add as
many more, and double that again, and our philosopher only laughs at his
inability to do a larger sum.  Such is the man at whom the vulgar scoff; he
seems to them as if he could not mind his feet.  'That is very true,
Socrates.'  But when he tries to draw the quick-witted lawyer out of his
pleas and rejoinders to the contemplation of absolute justice or injustice
in their own nature, or from the popular praises of wealthy kings to the
view of happiness and misery in themselves, or to the reasons why a man
should seek after the one and avoid the other, then the situation is
reversed; the little wretch turns giddy, and is ready to fall over the
precipice; his utterance becomes thick, and he makes himself ridiculous,
not to servant-maids, but to every man of liberal education.  Such are the
two pictures:  the one of the philosopher and gentleman, who may be excused
for not having learned how to make a bed, or cook up flatteries; the other,
a serviceable knave, who hardly knows how to wear his cloak,--still less
can he awaken harmonious thoughts or hymn virtue's praises.

'If the world, Socrates, were as ready to receive your words as I am, there
would be greater peace and less evil among mankind.'

Evil, Theodorus, must ever remain in this world to be the antagonist of
good, out of the way of the gods in heaven.  Wherefore also we should fly
away from ourselves to them; and to fly to them is to become like them; and
to become like them is to become holy, just and true.  But many live in the
old wives' fable of appearances; they think that you should follow virtue
in order that you may seem to be good.  And yet the truth is, that God is
righteous; and of men, he is most like him who is most righteous.  To know
this is wisdom; and in comparison of this the wisdom of the arts or the
seeming wisdom of politicians is mean and common.  The unrighteous man is
apt to pride himself on his cunning; when others call him rogue, he says to
himself:  'They only mean that I am one who deserves to live, and not a
mere burden of the earth.'  But he should reflect that his ignorance makes
his condition worse than if he knew.  For the penalty of injustice is not
death or stripes, but the fatal necessity of becoming more and more unjust.
Two patterns of life are set before him; the one blessed and divine, the
other godless and wretched; and he is growing more and more like the one
and unlike the other.  He does not see that if he continues in his cunning,
the place of innocence will not receive him after death.  And yet if such a
man has the courage to hear the argument out, he often becomes dissatisfied
with himself, and has no more strength in him than a child.--But we have
digressed enough.

'For my part, Socrates, I like the digressions better than the argument,
because I understand them better.'

To return.  When we left off, the Protagoreans and Heracliteans were
maintaining that the ordinances of the State were just, while they lasted.
But no one would maintain that the laws of the State were always good or
expedient, although this may be the intention of them.  For the expedient
has to do with the future, about which we are liable to mistake.  Now,
would Protagoras maintain that man is the measure not only of the present
and past, but of the future; and that there is no difference in the
judgments of men about the future?  Would an untrained man, for example, be
as likely to know when he is going to have a fever, as the physician who
attended him?  And if they differ in opinion, which of them is likely to be
right; or are they both right?  Is not a vine-grower a better judge of a
vintage which is not yet gathered, or a cook of a dinner which is in
preparation, or Protagoras of the probable effect of a speech than an
ordinary person?  The last example speaks 'ad hominen.'  For Protagoras
would never have amassed a fortune if every man could judge of the future
for himself.  He is, therefore, compelled to admit that he is a measure;
but I, who know nothing, am not equally convinced that I am.  This is one
way of refuting him; and he is refuted also by the authority which he
attributes to the opinions of others, who deny his opinions.  I am not
equally sure that we can disprove the truth of immediate states of feeling. 
But this leads us to the doctrine of the universal flux, about which a
battle-royal is always going on in the cities of Ionia.  'Yes; the
Ephesians are downright mad about the flux; they cannot stop to argue with
you, but are in perpetual motion, obedient to their text-books.  Their
restlessness is beyond expression, and if you ask any of them a question,
they will not answer, but dart at you some unintelligible saying, and
another and another, making no way either with themselves or with others;
for nothing is fixed in them or their ideas,--they are at war with fixed
principles.'  I suppose, Theodorus, that you have never seen them in time
of peace, when they discourse at leisure to their disciples?  'Disciples!
they have none; they are a set of uneducated fanatics, and each of them
says of the other that they have no knowledge.  We must trust to ourselves,
and not to them for the solution of the problem.'  Well, the doctrine is
old, being derived from the poets, who speak in a figure of Oceanus and
Tethys; the truth was once concealed, but is now revealed by the superior
wisdom of a later generation, and made intelligible to the cobbler, who, on
hearing that all is in motion, and not some things only, as he ignorantly
fancied, may be expected to fall down and worship his teachers.  And the
opposite doctrine must not be forgotten:--

'Alone being remains unmoved which is the name for all,'

as Parmenides affirms.  Thus we are in the midst of the fray; both parties
are dragging us to their side; and we are not certain which of them are in
the right; and if neither, then we shall be in a ridiculous position,
having to set up our own opinion against ancient and famous men.

Let us first approach the river-gods, or patrons of the flux.

When they speak of motion, must they not include two kinds of motion,
change of place and change of nature?--And all things must be supposed to
have both kinds of motion; for if not, the same things would be at rest and
in motion, which is contrary to their theory.  And did we not say, that all
sensations arise thus:  they move about between the agent and patient
together with a perception, and the patient ceases to be a perceiving power
and becomes a percipient, and the agent a quale instead of a quality; but
neither has any absolute existence?  But now we make the further discovery,
that neither white or whiteness, nor any sense or sensation, can be
predicated of anything, for they are in a perpetual flux.  And therefore we
must modify the doctrine of Theaetetus and Protagoras, by asserting further
that knowledge is and is not sensation; and of everything we must say
equally, that this is and is not, or becomes or becomes not.  And still the
word 'this' is not quite correct, for language fails in the attempt to
express their meaning.

At the close of the discussion, Theodorus claims to be released from the
argument, according to his agreement.  But Theaetetus insists that they
shall proceed to consider the doctrine of rest.  This is declined by
Socrates, who has too much reverence for the great Parmenides lightly to
attack him.  (We shall find that he returns to the doctrine of rest in the
Sophist; but at present he does not wish to be diverted from his main
purpose, which is, to deliver Theaetetus of his conception of knowledge.) 
He proceeds to interrogate him further.  When he says that 'knowledge is in
perception,' with what does he perceive?  The first answer is, that he
perceives sights with the eye, and sounds with the ear.  This leads
Socrates to make the reflection that nice distinctions of words are
sometimes pedantic, but sometimes necessary; and he proposes in this case
to substitute the word 'through' for 'with.'  For the senses are not like
the Trojan warriors in the horse, but have a common centre of perception,
in which they all meet.  This common principle is able to compare them with
one another, and must therefore be distinct from them (compare Republic). 
And as there are facts of sense which are perceived through the organs of
the body, there are also mathematical and other abstractions, such as
sameness and difference, likeness and unlikeness, which the soul perceives
by herself.  Being is the most universal of these abstractions.  The good
and the beautiful are abstractions of another kind, which exist in relation
and which above all others the mind perceives in herself, comparing within
her past, present, and future.  For example; we know a thing to be hard or
soft by the touch, of which the perception is given at birth to men and
animals.  But the essence of hardness or softness, or the fact that this
hardness is, and is the opposite of softness, is slowly learned by
reflection and experience.  Mere perception does not reach being, and
therefore fails of truth; and therefore has no share in knowledge.  But if
so, knowledge is not perception.  What then is knowledge?  The mind, when
occupied by herself with being, is said to have opinion--shall we say that
'Knowledge is true opinion'?  But still an old difficulty recurs; we ask
ourselves, 'How is false opinion possible?'  This difficulty may be stated
as follows:--

Either we know or do not know a thing (for the intermediate processes of
learning and forgetting need not at present be considered); and in thinking
or having an opinion, we must either know or not know that which we think,
and we cannot know and be ignorant at the same time; we cannot confuse one
thing which we do not know, with another thing which we do not know; nor
can we think that which we do not know to be that which we know, or that
which we know to be that which we do not know.  And what other case is
conceivable, upon the supposition that we either know or do not know all
things?  Let us try another answer in the sphere of being:  'When a man
thinks, and thinks that which is not.'  But would this hold in any parallel
case?  Can a man see and see nothing? or hear and hear nothing? or touch
and touch nothing?  Must he not see, hear, or touch some one existing
thing?  For if he thinks about nothing he does not think, and not thinking
he cannot think falsely.  And so the path of being is closed against us, as
well as the path of knowledge.  But may there not be 'heterodoxy,' or
transference of opinion;--I mean, may not one thing be supposed to be
another?  Theaetetus is confident that this must be 'the true falsehood,'
when a man puts good for evil or evil for good.  Socrates will not
discourage him by attacking the paradoxical expression 'true falsehood,'
but passes on.  The new notion involves a process of thinking about two
things, either together or alternately.  And thinking is the conversing of
the mind with herself, which is carried on in question and answer, until
she no longer doubts, but determines and forms an opinion.  And false
opinion consists in saying to yourself, that one thing is another.  But did
you ever say to yourself, that good is evil, or evil good?  Even in sleep,
did you ever imagine that odd was even?  Or did any man in his senses ever
fancy that an ox was a horse, or that two are one?  So that we can never
think one thing to be another; for you must not meet me with the verbal
quibble that one--eteron--is other--eteron (both 'one' and 'other' in Greek
are called 'other'--eteron).  He who has both the two things in his mind,
cannot misplace them; and he who has only one of them in his mind, cannot
misplace them--on either supposition transplacement is inconceivable.

But perhaps there may still be a sense in which we can think that which we
do not know to be that which we know:  e.g. Theaetetus may know Socrates,
but at a distance he may mistake another person for him.  This process may
be conceived by the help of an image.  Let us suppose that every man has in
his mind a block of wax of various qualities, the gift of Memory, the
mother of the Muses; and on this he receives the seal or stamp of those
sensations and perceptions which he wishes to remember.  That which he
succeeds in stamping is remembered and known by him as long as the
impression lasts; but that, of which the impression is rubbed out or
imperfectly made, is forgotten, and not known.  No one can think one thing
to be another, when he has the memorial or seal of both of these in his
soul, and a sensible impression of neither; or when he knows one and does
not know the other, and has no memorial or seal of the other; or when he
knows neither; or when he perceives both, or one and not the other, or
neither; or when he perceives and knows both, and identifies what he
perceives with what he knows (this is still more impossible); or when he
does not know one, and does not know and does not perceive the other; or
does not perceive one, and does not know and does not perceive the other;
or has no perception or knowledge of either--all these cases must be
excluded.  But he may err when he confuses what he knows or perceives, or
what he perceives and does not know, with what he knows, or what he knows
and perceives with what he knows and perceives.

Theaetetus is unable to follow these distinctions; which Socrates proceeds
to illustrate by examples, first of all remarking, that knowledge may exist
without perception, and perception without knowledge.  I may know Theodorus
and Theaetetus and not see them; I may see them, and not know them.  'That
I understand.'  But I could not mistake one for the other if I knew you
both, and had no perception of either; or if I knew one only, and perceived
neither; or if I knew and perceived neither, or in any other of the
excluded cases.  The only possibility of error is:  1st, when knowing you
and Theodorus, and having the impression of both of you on the waxen block,
I, seeing you both imperfectly and at a distance, put the foot in the wrong
shoe--that is to say, put the seal or stamp on the wrong object:  or 2ndly,
when knowing both of you I only see one; or when, seeing and knowing you
both, I fail to identify the impression and the object.  But there could be
no error when perception and knowledge correspond.

The waxen block in the heart of a man's soul, as I may say in the words of
Homer, who played upon the words ker and keros, may be smooth and deep, and
large enough, and then the signs are clearly marked and lasting, and do not
get confused.  But in the 'hairy heart,' as the all-wise poet sings, when
the wax is muddy or hard or moist, there is a corresponding confusion and
want of retentiveness; in the muddy and impure there is indistinctness, and
still more in the hard, for there the impressions have no depth of wax, and
in the moist they are too soon effaced.  Yet greater is the indistinctness
when they are all jolted together in a little soul, which is narrow and has
no room.  These are the sort of natures which have false opinion; from
stupidity they see and hear and think amiss; and this is falsehood and
ignorance.  Error, then, is a confusion of thought and sense.

Theaetetus is delighted with this explanation.  But Socrates has no sooner
found the new solution than he sinks into a fit of despondency.  For an
objection occurs to him:--May there not be errors where there is no
confusion of mind and sense? e.g. in numbers.  No one can confuse the man
whom he has in his thoughts with the horse which he has in his thoughts,
but he may err in the addition of five and seven.  And observe that these
are purely mental conceptions.  Thus we are involved once more in the
dilemma of saying, either that there is no such thing as false opinion, or
that a man knows what he does not know.

We are at our wit's end, and may therefore be excused for making a bold
diversion.  All this time we have been repeating the words 'know,'
'understand,' yet we do not know what knowledge is.  'Why, Socrates, how
can you argue at all without using them?'  Nay, but the true hero of
dialectic would have forbidden me to use them until I had explained them.
And I must explain them now.  The verb 'to know' has two senses, to have
and to possess knowledge, and I distinguish 'having' from 'possessing.'  A
man may possess a garment which he does not wear; or he may have wild birds
in an aviary; these in one sense he possesses, and in another he has none
of them.  Let this aviary be an image of the mind, as the waxen block was;
when we are young, the aviary is empty; after a time the birds are put in;
for under this figure we may describe different forms of knowledge;--there
are some of them in groups, and some single, which are flying about
everywhere; and let us suppose a hunt after the science of odd and even, or
some other science.  The possession of the birds is clearly not the same as
the having them in the hand.  And the original chase of them is not the
same as taking them in the hand when they are already caged.

This distinction between use and possession saves us from the absurdity of
supposing that we do not know what we know, because we may know in one
sense, i.e. possess, what we do not know in another, i.e. use.  But have we
not escaped one difficulty only to encounter a greater?  For how can the
exchange of two kinds of knowledge ever become false opinion?  As well
might we suppose that ignorance could make a man know, or that blindness
could make him see.  Theaetetus suggests that in the aviary there may be
flying about mock birds, or forms of ignorance, and we put forth our hands
and grasp ignorance, when we are intending to grasp knowledge.  But how can
he who knows the forms of knowledge and the forms of ignorance imagine one
to be the other?  Is there some other form of knowledge which distinguishes
them? and another, and another?  Thus we go round and round in a circle and
make no progress.

All this confusion arises out of our attempt to explain false opinion
without having explained knowledge.  What then is knowledge?  Theaetetus
repeats that knowledge is true opinion.  But this seems to be refuted by
the instance of orators and judges.  For surely the orator cannot convey a
true knowledge of crimes at which the judges were not present; he can only
persuade them, and the judge may form a true opinion and truly judge.  But
if true opinion were knowledge they could not have judged without
knowledge.

Once more.  Theaetetus offers a definition which he has heard:  Knowledge
is true opinion accompanied by definition or explanation.  Socrates has had
a similar dream, and has further heard that the first elements are names
only, and that definition or explanation begins when they are combined; the
letters are unknown, the syllables or combinations are known.  But this new
hypothesis when tested by the letters of the alphabet is found to break
down.  The first syllable of Socrates' name is SO.  But what is SO?  Two
letters, S and O, a sibilant and a vowel, of which no further explanation
can be given.  And how can any one be ignorant of either of them, and yet
know both of them?  There is, however, another alternative:--We may suppose
that the syllable has a separate form or idea distinct from the letters or
parts.  The all of the parts may not be the whole.  Theaetetus is very much
inclined to adopt this suggestion, but when interrogated by Socrates he is
unable to draw any distinction between the whole and all the parts.  And if
the syllables have no parts, then they are those original elements of which
there is no explanation.  But how can the syllable be known if the letter
remains unknown?  In learning to read as children, we are first taught the
letters and then the syllables.  And in music, the notes, which are the
letters, have a much more distinct meaning to us than the combination of
them.

Once more, then, we must ask the meaning of the statement, that 'Knowledge
is right opinion, accompanied by explanation or definition.'  Explanation
may mean, (1) the reflection or expression of a man's thoughts--but every
man who is not deaf and dumb is able to express his thoughts--or (2) the
enumeration of the elements of which anything is composed.  A man may have
a true opinion about a waggon, but then, and then only, has he knowledge of
a waggon when he is able to enumerate the hundred planks of Hesiod.  Or he
may know the syllables of the name Theaetetus, but not the letters; yet not
until he knows both can he be said to have knowledge as well as opinion. 
But on the other hand he may know the syllable 'The' in the name
Theaetetus, yet he may be mistaken about the same syllable in the name
Theodorus, and in learning to read we often make such mistakes.  And even
if he could write out all the letters and syllables of your name in order,
still he would only have right opinion.  Yet there may be a third meaning
of the definition, besides the image or expression of the mind, and the
enumeration of the elements, viz. (3) perception of difference.

For example, I may see a man who has eyes, nose, and mouth;--that will not
distinguish him from any other man.  Or he may have a snub-nose and
prominent eyes;--that will not distinguish him from myself and you and
others who are like me.  But when I see a certain kind of snub-nosedness,
then I recognize Theaetetus.  And having this sign of difference, I have
knowledge.  But have I knowledge or opinion of this difference; if I have
only opinion I have not knowledge; if I have knowledge we assume a disputed
term; for knowledge will have to be defined as right opinion with knowledge
of difference.

And so, Theaetetus, knowledge is neither perception nor true opinion, nor
yet definition accompanying true opinion.  And I have shown that the
children of your brain are not worth rearing.  Are you still in labour, or
have you brought all you have to say about knowledge to the birth?  If you
have any more thoughts, you will be the better for having got rid of these;
or if you have none, you will be the better for not fancying that you know
what you do not know.  Observe the limits of my art, which, like my
mother's, is an art of midwifery; I do not pretend to compare with the good
and wise of this and other ages.

And now I go to meet Meletus at the porch of the King Archon; but to-morrow
I shall hope to see you again, Theodorus, at this place.

...

I. The saying of Theaetetus, that 'Knowledge is sensible perception,' may
be assumed to be a current philosophical opinion of the age.  'The
ancients,' as Aristotle (De Anim.) says, citing a verse of Empedocles,
'affirmed knowledge to be the same as perception.'  We may now examine
these words, first, with reference to their place in the history of
philosophy, and secondly, in relation to modern speculations.

(a)  In the age of Socrates the mind was passing from the object to the
subject.  The same impulse which a century before had led men to form
conceptions of the world, now led them to frame general notions of the
human faculties and feelings, such as memory, opinion, and the like.  The
simplest of these is sensation, or sensible perception, by which Plato
seems to mean the generalized notion of feelings and impressions of sense,
without determining whether they are conscious or not.

The theory that 'Knowledge is sensible perception' is the antithesis of
that which derives knowledge from the mind (Theaet.), or which assumes the
existence of ideas independent of the mind (Parm.).  Yet from their extreme
abstraction these theories do not represent the opposite poles of thought
in the same way that the corresponding differences would in modern
philosophy.  The most ideal and the most sensational have a tendency to
pass into one another; Heracleitus, like his great successor Hegel, has
both aspects.  The Eleatic isolation of Being and the Megarian or Cynic
isolation of individuals are placed in the same class by Plato (Soph.); and
the same principle which is the symbol of motion to one mind is the symbol
of rest to another.  The Atomists, who are sometimes regarded as the
Materialists of Plato, denied the reality of sensation.  And in the ancient
as well as the modern world there were reactions from theory to experience,
from ideas to sense.  This is a point of view from which the philosophy of
sensation presented great attraction to the ancient thinker.  Amid the
conflict of ideas and the variety of opinions, the impression of sense
remained certain and uniform.  Hardness, softness, cold, heat, etc. are not
absolutely the same to different persons, but the art of measuring could at
any rate reduce them all to definite natures (Republic).  Thus the doctrine
that knowledge is perception supplies or seems to supply a firm standing
ground.  Like the other notions of the earlier Greek philosophy, it was
held in a very simple way, without much basis of reasoning, and without
suggesting the questions which naturally arise in our own minds on the same
subject.

(b)  The fixedness of impressions of sense furnishes a link of connexion
between ancient and modern philosophy.  The modern thinker often repeats
the parallel axiom, 'All knowledge is experience.'  He means to say that
the outward and not the inward is both the original source and the final
criterion of truth, because the outward can be observed and analyzed; the
inward is only known by external results, and is dimly perceived by each
man for himself.  In what does this differ from the saying of Theaetetus? 
Chiefly in this--that the modern term 'experience,' while implying a point
of departure in sense and a return to sense, also includes all the
processes of reasoning and imagination which have intervened.  The
necessary connexion between them by no means affords a measure of the
relative degree of importance which is to be ascribed to either element. 
For the inductive portion of any science may be small, as in mathematics or
ethics, compared with that which the mind has attained by reasoning and
reflection on a very few facts.

II.  The saying that 'All knowledge is sensation' is identified by Plato
with the Protagorean thesis that 'Man is the measure of all things.'  The
interpretation which Protagoras himself is supposed to give of these latter
words is:  'Things are to me as they appear to me, and to you as they
appear to you.'  But there remains still an ambiguity both in the text and
in the explanation, which has to be cleared up.  Did Protagoras merely mean
to assert the relativity of knowledge to the human mind?  Or did he mean to
deny that there is an objective standard of truth?

These two questions have not been always clearly distinguished; the
relativity of knowledge has been sometimes confounded with uncertainty. 
The untutored mind is apt to suppose that objects exist independently of
the human faculties, because they really exist independently of the
faculties of any individual. In the same way, knowledge appears to be a
body of truths stored up in books, which when once ascertained are
independent of the discoverer.  Further consideration shows us that these
truths are not really independent of the mind; there is an adaptation of
one to the other, of the eye to the object of sense, of the mind to the
conception.  There would be no world, if there neither were nor ever had
been any one to perceive the world.  A slight effort of reflection enables
us to understand this; but no effort of reflection will enable us to pass
beyond the limits of our own faculties, or to imagine the relation or
adaptation of objects to the mind to be different from that of which we
have experience.  There are certain laws of language and logic to which we
are compelled to conform, and to which our ideas naturally adapt
themselves; and we can no more get rid of them than we can cease to be
ourselves.  The absolute and infinite, whether explained as self-existence,
or as the totality of human thought, or as the Divine nature, if known to
us at all, cannot escape from the category of relation.

But because knowledge is subjective or relative to the mind, we are not to
suppose that we are therefore deprived of any of the tests or criteria of
truth.  One man still remains wiser than another, a more accurate observer
and relater of facts, a truer measure of the proportions of knowledge.  The
nature of testimony is not altered, nor the verification of causes by
prescribed methods less certain.  Again, the truth must often come to a man
through others, according to the measure of his capacity and education. 
But neither does this affect the testimony, whether written or oral, which
he knows by experience to be trustworthy.  He cannot escape from the laws
of his own mind; and he cannot escape from the further accident of being
dependent for his knowledge on others.  But still this is no reason why he
should always be in doubt; of many personal, of many historical and
scientific facts he may be absolutely assured.  And having such a mass of
acknowledged truth in the mathematical and physical, not to speak of the
moral sciences, the moderns have certainly no reason to acquiesce in the
statement that truth is appearance only, or that there is no difference
between appearance and truth.

The relativity of knowledge is a truism to us, but was a great
psychological discovery in the fifth century before Christ.  Of this
discovery, the first distinct assertion is contained in the thesis of
Protagoras.  Probably he had no intention either of denying or affirming an
objective standard of truth.  He did not consider whether man in the higher
or man in the lower sense was a 'measure of all things.'  Like other great
thinkers, he was absorbed with one idea, and that idea was the absoluteness
of perception.  Like Socrates, he seemed to see that philosophy must be
brought back from 'nature' to 'truth,' from the world to man.  But he did
not stop to analyze whether he meant 'man' in the concrete or man in the
abstract, any man or some men, 'quod semper quod ubique' or individual
private judgment.  Such an analysis lay beyond his sphere of thought; the
age before Socrates had not arrived at these distinctions.  Like the
Cynics, again, he discarded knowledge in any higher sense than perception. 
For 'truer' or 'wiser' he substituted the word 'better,' and is not
unwilling to admit that both states and individuals are capable of
practical improvement.  But this improvement does not arise from
intellectual enlightenment, nor yet from the exertion of the will, but from
a change of circumstances and impressions; and he who can effect this
change in himself or others may be deemed a philosopher.  In the mode of
effecting it, while agreeing with Socrates and the Cynics in the importance
which he attaches to practical life, he is at variance with both of them. 
To suppose that practice can be divorced from speculation, or that we may
do good without caring about truth, is by no means singular, either in
philosophy or life.  The singularity of this, as of some other (so-called)
sophistical doctrines, is the frankness with which they are avowed, instead
of being veiled, as in modern times, under ambiguous and convenient
phrases.

Plato appears to treat Protagoras much as he himself is treated by
Aristotle; that is to say, he does not attempt to understand him from his
own point of view.  But he entangles him in the meshes of a more advanced
logic.  To which Protagoras is supposed to reply by Megarian quibbles,
which destroy logic, 'Not only man, but each man, and each man at each
moment.'  In the arguments about sight and memory there is a palpable
unfairness which is worthy of the great 'brainless brothers,' Euthydemus
and Dionysodorus, and may be compared with the egkekalummenos ('obvelatus')
of Eubulides.  For he who sees with one eye only cannot be truly said both
to see and not to see; nor is memory, which is liable to forget, the
immediate knowledge to which Protagoras applies the term.  Theodorus justly
charges Socrates with going beyond the truth; and Protagoras has equally
right on his side when he protests against Socrates arguing from the common
use of words, which 'the vulgar pervert in all manner of ways.'

III.  The theory of Protagoras is connected by Aristotle as well as Plato
with the flux of Heracleitus.  But Aristotle is only following Plato, and
Plato, as we have already seen, did not mean to imply that such a connexion
was admitted by Protagoras himself.  His metaphysical genius saw or seemed
to see a common tendency in them, just as the modern historian of ancient
philosophy might perceive a parallelism between two thinkers of which they
were probably unconscious themselves.  We must remember throughout that
Plato is not speaking of Heracleitus, but of the Heracliteans, who
succeeded him; nor of the great original ideas of the master, but of the
Eristic into which they had degenerated a hundred years later.  There is
nothing in the fragments of Heracleitus which at all justifies Plato's
account of him.  His philosophy may be resolved into two elements--first,
change, secondly, law or measure pervading the change:  these he saw
everywhere, and often expressed in strange mythological symbols.  But he
has no analysis of sensible perception such as Plato attributes to him; nor
is there any reason to suppose that he pushed his philosophy into that
absolute negation in which Heracliteanism was sunk in the age of Plato.  He
never said that 'change means every sort of change;' and he expressly
distinguished between 'the general and particular understanding.'  Like a
poet, he surveyed the elements of mythology, nature, thought, which lay
before him, and sometimes by the light of genius he saw or seemed to see a
mysterious principle working behind them.  But as has been the case with
other great philosophers, and with Plato and Aristotle themselves, what was
really permanent and original could not be understood by the next
generation, while a perverted logic carried out his chance expressions with
an illogical consistency.  His simple and noble thoughts, like those of the
great Eleatic, soon degenerated into a mere strife of words.  And when thus
reduced to mere words, they seem to have exercised a far wider influence in
the cities of Ionia (where the people 'were mad about them') than in the
life-time of Heracleitus--a phenomenon which, though at first sight
singular, is not without a parallel in the history of philosophy and
theology.

It is this perverted form of the Heraclitean philosophy which is supposed
to effect the final overthrow of Protagorean sensationalism.  For if all
things are changing at every moment, in all sorts of ways, then there is
nothing fixed or defined at all, and therefore no sensible perception, nor
any true word by which that or anything else can be described.  Of course
Protagoras would not have admitted the justice of this argument any more
than Heracleitus would have acknowledged the 'uneducated fanatics' who
appealed to his writings.  He might have said, 'The excellent Socrates has
first confused me with Heracleitus, and Heracleitus with his Ephesian
successors, and has then disproved the existence both of knowledge and
sensation.  But I am not responsible for what I never said, nor will I
admit that my common-sense account of knowledge can be overthrown by
unintelligible Heraclitean paradoxes.'

IV.  Still at the bottom of the arguments there remains a truth, that
knowledge is something more than sensible perception;--this alone would not
distinguish man from a tadpole.  The absoluteness of sensations at each
moment destroys the very consciousness of sensations (compare Phileb.), or
the power of comparing them.  The senses are not mere holes in a 'Trojan
horse,' but the organs of a presiding nature, in which they meet.  A great
advance has been made in psychology when the senses are recognized as
organs of sense, and we are admitted to see or feel 'through them' and not
'by them,' a distinction of words which, as Socrates observes, is by no
means pedantic.  A still further step has been made when the most abstract
notions, such as Being and Not-being, sameness and difference, unity and
plurality, are acknowledged to be the creations of the mind herself,
working upon the feelings or impressions of sense.  In this manner Plato
describes the process of acquiring them, in the words 'Knowledge consists
not in the feelings or affections (pathemasi), but in the process of
reasoning about them (sullogismo).'  Here, is in the Parmenides, he means
something not really different from generalization.  As in the Sophist, he
is laying the foundation of a rational psychology, which is to supersede
the Platonic reminiscence of Ideas as well as the Eleatic Being and the
individualism of Megarians and Cynics.

V.  Having rejected the doctrine that 'Knowledge is perception,' we now
proceed to look for a definition of knowledge in the sphere of opinion. 
But here we are met by a singular difficulty:  How is false opinion
possible?  For we must either know or not know that which is presented to
the mind or to sense.  We of course should answer at once:  'No; the
alternative is not necessary, for there may be degrees of knowledge; and we
may know and have forgotten, or we may be learning, or we may have a
general but not a particular knowledge, or we may know but not be able to
explain;' and many other ways may be imagined in which we know and do not
know at the same time.  But these answers belong to a later stage of
metaphysical discussion; whereas the difficulty in question naturally
arises owing to the childhood of the human mind, like the parallel
difficulty respecting Not-being.  Men had only recently arrived at the
notion of opinion; they could not at once define the true and pass beyond
into the false.  The very word doxa was full of ambiguity, being sometimes,
as in the Eleatic philosophy, applied to the sensible world, and again used
in the more ordinary sense of opinion.  There is no connexion between
sensible appearance and probability, and yet both of them met in the word
doxa, and could hardly be disengaged from one another in the mind of the
Greek living in the fifth or fourth century B.C.  To this was often added,
as at the end of the fifth book of the Republic, the idea of relation,
which is equally distinct from either of them; also a fourth notion, the
conclusion of the dialectical process, the making up of the mind after she
has been 'talking to herself' (Theat.).

We are not then surprised that the sphere of opinion and of Not-being
should be a dusky, half-lighted place (Republic), belonging neither to the
old world of sense and imagination, nor to the new world of reflection and
reason.  Plato attempts to clear up this darkness.  In his accustomed
manner he passes from the lower to the higher, without omitting the
intermediate stages.  This appears to be the reason why he seeks for the
definition of knowledge first in the sphere of opinion.  Hereafter we shall
find that something more than opinion is required.

False opinion is explained by Plato at first as a confusion of mind and
sense, which arises when the impression on the mind does not correspond to
the impression made on the senses.  It is obvious that this explanation
(supposing the distinction between impressions on the mind and impressions
on the senses to be admitted) does not account for all forms of error; and
Plato has excluded himself from the consideration of the greater number, by
designedly omitting the intermediate processes of learning and forgetting;
nor does he include fallacies in the use of language or erroneous
inferences.  But he is struck by one possibility of error, which is not
covered by his theory, viz. errors in arithmetic.  For in numbers and
calculation there is no combination of thought and sense, and yet errors
may often happen.  Hence he is led to discard the explanation which might
nevertheless have been supposed to hold good (for anything which he says to
the contrary) as a rationale of error, in the case of facts derived from
sense.

Another attempt is made to explain false opinion by assigning to error a
sort of positive existence.  But error or ignorance is essentially
negative--a not-knowing; if we knew an error, we should be no longer in
error.  We may veil our difficulty under figures of speech, but these,
although telling arguments with the multitude, can never be the real
foundation of a system of psychology.  Only they lead us to dwell upon
mental phenomena which if expressed in an abstract form would not be
realized by us at all.  The figure of the mind receiving impressions is one
of those images which have rooted themselves for ever in language.  It may
or may not be a 'gracious aid' to thought; but it cannot be got rid of. 
The other figure of the enclosure is also remarkable as affording the first
hint of universal all-pervading ideas,--a notion further carried out in the
Sophist.  This is implied in the birds, some in flocks, some solitary,
which fly about anywhere and everywhere.  Plato discards both figures, as
not really solving the question which to us appears so simple:  'How do we
make mistakes?'  The failure of the enquiry seems to show that we should
return to knowledge, and begin with that; and we may afterwards proceed,
with a better hope of success, to the examination of opinion.

But is true opinion really distinct from knowledge?  The difference between
these he seeks to establish by an argument, which to us appears singular
and unsatisfactory.  The existence of true opinion is proved by the
rhetoric of the law courts, which cannot give knowledge, but may give true
opinion.  The rhetorician cannot put the judge or juror in possession of
all the facts which prove an act of violence, but he may truly persuade
them of the commission of such an act.  Here the idea of true opinion seems
to be a right conclusion from imperfect knowledge.  But the correctness of
such an opinion will be purely accidental; and is really the effect of one
man, who has the means of knowing, persuading another who has not.  Plato
would have done better if he had said that true opinion was a contradiction
in terms.

Assuming the distinction between knowledge and opinion, Theaetetus, in
answer to Socrates, proceeds to define knowledge as true opinion, with
definite or rational explanation.  This Socrates identifies with another
and different theory, of those who assert that knowledge first begins with
a proposition.

The elements may be perceived by sense, but they are names, and cannot be
defined.  When we assign to them some predicate, they first begin to have a
meaning (onomaton sumploke logou ousia).  This seems equivalent to saying,
that the individuals of sense become the subject of knowledge when they are
regarded as they are in nature in relation to other individuals.

Yet we feel a difficulty in following this new hypothesis.  For must not
opinion be equally expressed in a proposition?  The difference between true
and false opinion is not the difference between the particular and the
universal, but between the true universal and the false.  Thought may be as
much at fault as sight.  When we place individuals under a class, or assign
to them attributes, this is not knowledge, but a very rudimentary process
of thought; the first generalization of all, without which language would
be impossible.  And has Plato kept altogether clear of a confusion, which
the analogous word logos tends to create, of a proposition and a
definition?  And is not the confusion increased by the use of the analogous
term 'elements,' or 'letters'?  For there is no real resemblance between
the relation of letters to a syllable, and of the terms to a proposition.

Plato, in the spirit of the Megarian philosophy, soon discovers a flaw in
the explanation.  For how can we know a compound of which the simple
elements are unknown to us?  Can two unknowns make a known?  Can a whole be
something different from the parts?  The answer of experience is that they
can; for we may know a compound, which we are unable to analyze into its
elements; and all the parts, when united, may be more than all the parts
separated:  e.g. the number four, or any other number, is more than the
units which are contained in it; any chemical compound is more than and
different from the simple elements.  But ancient philosophy in this, as in
many other instances, proceeding by the path of mental analysis, was
perplexed by doubts which warred against the plainest facts.

Three attempts to explain the new definition of knowledge still remain to
be considered.  They all of them turn on the explanation of logos.  The
first account of the meaning of the word is the reflection of thought in
speech--a sort of nominalism 'La science est une langue bien faite.'  But
anybody who is not dumb can say what he thinks; therefore mere speech
cannot be knowledge.  And yet we may observe, that there is in this
explanation an element of truth which is not recognized by Plato; viz. that
truth and thought are inseparable from language, although mere expression
in words is not truth.  The second explanation of logos is the enumeration
of the elementary parts of the complex whole.  But this is only definition
accompanied with right opinion, and does not yet attain to the certainty of
knowledge.  Plato does not mention the greater objection, which is, that
the enumeration of particulars is endless; such a definition would be based
on no principle, and would not help us at all in gaining a common idea. 
The third is the best explanation,--the possession of a characteristic
mark, which seems to answer to the logical definition by genus and
difference.  But this, again, is equally necessary for right opinion; and
we have already determined, although not on very satisfactory grounds, that
knowledge must be distinguished from opinion.  A better distinction is
drawn between them in the Timaeus.  They might be opposed as philosophy and
rhetoric, and as conversant respectively with necessary and contingent
matter.  But no true idea of the nature of either of them, or of their
relation to one another, could be framed until science obtained a content. 
The ancient philosophers in the age of Plato thought of science only as
pure abstraction, and to this opinion stood in no relation.

Like Theaetetus, we have attained to no definite result.  But an
interesting phase of ancient philosophy has passed before us.  And the
negative result is not to be despised.  For on certain subjects, and in
certain states of knowledge, the work of negation or clearing the ground
must go on, perhaps for a generation, before the new structure can begin to
rise.  Plato saw the necessity of combating the illogical logic of the
Megarians and Eristics.  For the completion of the edifice, he makes
preparation in the Theaetetus, and crowns the work in the Sophist.

Many (1) fine expressions, and (2) remarks full of wisdom, (3) also germs
of a metaphysic of the future, are scattered up and down in the dialogue.
Such, for example, as (1) the comparison of Theaetetus' progress in
learning to the 'noiseless flow of a river of oil'; the satirical touch,
'flavouring a sauce or fawning speech'; or the remarkable expression, 'full
of impure dialectic'; or the lively images under which the argument is
described,--'the flood of arguments pouring in,' the fresh discussions
'bursting in like a band of revellers.'  (2) As illustrations of the second
head, may be cited the remark of Socrates, that 'distinctions of words,
although sometimes pedantic, are also necessary'; or the fine touch in the
character of the lawyer, that 'dangers came upon him when the tenderness of
youth was unequal to them'; or the description of the manner in which the
spirit is broken in a wicked man who listens to reproof until he becomes
like a child; or the punishment of the wicked, which is not physical
suffering, but the perpetual companionship of evil (compare Gorgias); or
the saying, often repeated by Aristotle and others, that 'philosophy begins
in wonder, for Iris is the child of Thaumas'; or the superb contempt with
which the philosopher takes down the pride of wealthy landed proprietors by
comparison of the whole earth.  (3) Important metaphysical ideas are:  a.
the conception of thought, as the mind talking to herself; b. the notion of
a common sense, developed further by Aristotle, and the explicit
declaration, that the mind gains her conceptions of Being, sameness,
number, and the like, from reflection on herself; c. the excellent
distinction of Theaetetus (which Socrates, speaking with emphasis, 'leaves
to grow') between seeing the forms or hearing the sounds of words in a
foreign language, and understanding the meaning of them; and d. the
distinction of Socrates himself between 'having' and 'possessing'
knowledge, in which the answer to the whole discussion appears to be
contained.

...

There is a difference between ancient and modern psychology, and we have a
difficulty in explaining one in the terms of the other.  To us the inward
and outward sense and the inward and outward worlds of which they are the
organs are parted by a wall, and appear as if they could never be
confounded.  The mind is endued with faculties, habits, instincts, and a
personality or consciousness in which they are bound together.  Over
against these are placed forms, colours, external bodies coming into
contact with our own body.  We speak of a subject which is ourselves, of an
object which is all the rest.  These are separable in thought, but united
in any act of sensation, reflection, or volition.  As there are various
degrees in which the mind may enter into or be abstracted from the
operations of sense, so there are various points at which this separation
or union may be supposed to occur.  And within the sphere of mind the
analogy of sense reappears; and we distinguish not only external objects,
but objects of will and of knowledge which we contrast with them.  These
again are comprehended in a higher object, which reunites with the subject.
A multitude of abstractions are created by the efforts of successive
thinkers which become logical determinations; and they have to be arranged
in order, before the scheme of thought is complete.  The framework of the
human intellect is not the peculium of an individual, but the joint work of
many who are of all ages and countries.  What we are in mind is due, not
merely to our physical, but to our mental antecedents which we trace in
history, and more especially in the history of philosophy.  Nor can mental
phenomena be truly explained either by physiology or by the observation of
consciousness apart from their history.  They have a growth of their own,
like the growth of a flower, a tree, a human being.  They may be conceived
as of themselves constituting a common mind, and having a sort of personal
identity in which they coexist.

So comprehensive is modern psychology, seeming to aim at constructing anew
the entire world of thought.  And prior to or simultaneously with this
construction a negative process has to be carried on, a clearing away of
useless abstractions which we have inherited from the past.  Many erroneous
conceptions of the mind derived from former philosophies have found their
way into language, and we with difficulty disengage ourselves from them. 
Mere figures of speech have unconsciously influenced the minds of great
thinkers.  Also there are some distinctions, as, for example, that of the
will and of the reason, and of the moral and intellectual faculties, which
are carried further than is justified by experience.  Any separation of
things which we cannot see or exactly define, though it may be necessary,
is a fertile source of error.  The division of the mind into faculties or
powers or virtues is too deeply rooted in language to be got rid of, but it
gives a false impression.  For if we reflect on ourselves we see that all
our faculties easily pass into one another, and are bound together in a
single mind or consciousness; but this mental unity is apt to be concealed
from us by the distinctions of language.

A profusion of words and ideas has obscured rather than enlightened mental
science.  It is hard to say how many fallacies have arisen from the
representation of the mind as a box, as a 'tabula rasa,' a book, a mirror,
and the like.  It is remarkable how Plato in the Theaetetus, after having
indulged in the figure of the waxen tablet and the decoy, afterwards
discards them.  The mind is also represented by another class of images, as
the spring of a watch, a motive power, a breath, a stream, a succession of
points or moments.  As Plato remarks in the Cratylus, words expressive of
motion as well as of rest are employed to describe the faculties and
operations of the mind; and in these there is contained another store of
fallacies.  Some shadow or reflection of the body seems always to adhere to
our thoughts about ourselves, and mental processes are hardly distinguished
in language from bodily ones.  To see or perceive are used indifferently of
both; the words intuition, moral sense, common sense, the mind's eye, are
figures of speech transferred from one to the other.  And many other words
used in early poetry or in sacred writings to express the works of mind
have a materialistic sound; for old mythology was allied to sense, and the
distinction of matter and mind had not as yet arisen.  Thus materialism
receives an illusive aid from language; and both in philosophy and religion
the imaginary figure or association easily takes the place of real
knowledge.

Again, there is the illusion of looking into our own minds as if our
thoughts or feelings were written down in a book.  This is another figure
of speech, which might be appropriately termed 'the fallacy of the looking-
glass.'  We cannot look at the mind unless we have the eye which sees, and
we can only look, not into, but out of the mind at the thoughts, words,
actions of ourselves and others.  What we dimly recognize within us is not
experience, but rather the suggestion of an experience, which we may
gather, if we will, from the observation of the world.  The memory has but
a feeble recollection of what we were saying or doing a few weeks or a few
months ago, and still less of what we were thinking or feeling.  This is
one among many reasons why there is so little self-knowledge among mankind;
they do not carry with them the thought of what they are or have been.  The
so-called 'facts of consciousness' are equally evanescent; they are facts
which nobody ever saw, and which can neither be defined nor described.  Of
the three laws of thought the first (All A = A) is an identical
proposition--that is to say, a mere word or symbol claiming to be a
proposition:  the two others (Nothing can be A and not A, and Everything is
either A or not A) are untrue, because they exclude degrees and also the
mixed modes and double aspects under which truth is so often presented to
us.  To assert that man is man is unmeaning; to say that he is free or
necessary and cannot be both is a half truth only.  These are a few of the
entanglements which impede the natural course of human thought.  Lastly,
there is the fallacy which lies still deeper, of regarding the individual
mind apart from the universal, or either, as a self-existent entity apart
from the ideas which are contained in them.

In ancient philosophies the analysis of the mind is still rudimentary and
imperfect.  It naturally began with an effort to disengage the universal
from sense--this was the first lifting up of the mist.  It wavered between
object and subject, passing imperceptibly from one or Being to mind and
thought.  Appearance in the outward object was for a time indistinguishable
from opinion in the subject.  At length mankind spoke of knowing as well as
of opining or perceiving.  But when the word 'knowledge' was found how was
it to be explained or defined?  It was not an error, it was a step in the
right direction, when Protagoras said that 'Man is the measure of all
things,' and that 'All knowledge is perception.'  This was the subjective
which corresponded to the objective 'All is flux.'  But the thoughts of men
deepened, and soon they began to be aware that knowledge was neither sense,
nor yet opinion--with or without explanation; nor the expression of
thought, nor the enumeration of parts, nor the addition of characteristic
marks.  Motion and rest were equally ill adapted to express its nature,
although both must in some sense be attributed to it; it might be described
more truly as the mind conversing with herself; the discourse of reason;
the hymn of dialectic, the science of relations, of ideas, of the so-called
arts and sciences, of the one, of the good, of the all:--this is the way
along which Plato is leading us in his later dialogues.  In its higher
signification it was the knowledge, not of men, but of gods, perfect and
all sufficing:--like other ideals always passing out of sight, and
nevertheless present to the mind of Aristotle as well as Plato, and the
reality to which they were both tending.  For Aristotle as well as Plato
would in modern phraseology have been termed a mystic; and like him would
have defined the higher philosophy to be 'Knowledge of being or essence,'--
words to which in our own day we have a difficulty in attaching a meaning.

Yet, in spite of Plato and his followers, mankind have again and again
returned to a sensational philosophy.  As to some of the early thinkers,
amid the fleetings of sensible objects, ideas alone seemed to be fixed, so
to a later generation amid the fluctuation of philosophical opinions the
only fixed points appeared to be outward objects.  Any pretence of
knowledge which went beyond them implied logical processes, of the
correctness of which they had no assurance and which at best were only
probable.  The mind, tired of wandering, sought to rest on firm ground;
when the idols of philosophy and language were stripped off, the perception
of outward objects alone remained.  The ancient Epicureans never asked
whether the comparison of these with one another did not involve principles
of another kind which were above and beyond them.  In like manner the
modern inductive philosophy forgot to enquire into the meaning of
experience, and did not attempt to form a conception of outward objects
apart from the mind, or of the mind apart from them.  Soon objects of sense
were merged in sensations and feelings, but feelings and sensations were
still unanalyzed.  At last we return to the doctrine attributed by Plato to
Protagoras, that the mind is only a succession of momentary perceptions. 
At this point the modern philosophy of experience forms an alliance with
ancient scepticism.

The higher truths of philosophy and religion are very far removed from
sense.  Admitting that, like all other knowledge, they are derived from
experience, and that experience is ultimately resolvable into facts which
come to us through the eye and ear, still their origin is a mere accident
which has nothing to do with their true nature.  They are universal and
unseen; they belong to all times--past, present, and future.  Any worthy
notion of mind or reason includes them.  The proof of them is, 1st, their
comprehensiveness and consistency with one another; 2ndly, their agreement
with history and experience.  But sensation is of the present only, is
isolated, is and is not in successive moments.  It takes the passing hour
as it comes, following the lead of the eye or ear instead of the command of
reason.  It is a faculty which man has in common with the animals, and in
which he is inferior to many of them.  The importance of the senses in us
is that they are the apertures of the mind, doors and windows through which
we take in and make our own the materials of knowledge.  Regarded in any
other point of view sensation is of all mental acts the most trivial and
superficial.  Hence the term 'sensational' is rightly used to express what
is shallow in thought and feeling.

We propose in what follows, first of all, like Plato in the Theaetetus, to
analyse sensation, and secondly to trace the connexion between theories of
sensation and a sensational or Epicurean philosophy.

Paragraph I.  We, as well as the ancients, speak of the five senses, and of
a sense, or common sense, which is the abstraction of them.  The term
'sense' is also used metaphorically, both in ancient and modern philosophy,
to express the operations of the mind which are immediate or intuitive.  Of
the five senses, two--the sight and the hearing--are of a more subtle and
complex nature, while two others--the smell and the taste--seem to be only
more refined varieties of touch.  All of them are passive, and by this are
distinguished from the active faculty of speech:  they receive impressions,
but do not produce them, except in so far as they are objects of sense
themselves.

Physiology speaks to us of the wonderful apparatus of nerves, muscles,
tissues, by which the senses are enabled to fulfil their functions.  It
traces the connexion, though imperfectly, of the bodily organs with the
operations of the mind.  Of these latter, it seems rather to know the
conditions than the causes.  It can prove to us that without the brain we
cannot think, and that without the eye we cannot see:  and yet there is far
more in thinking and seeing than is given by the brain and the eye.  It
observes the 'concomitant variations' of body and mind.  Psychology, on the
other hand, treats of the same subject regarded from another point of view. 
It speaks of the relation of the senses to one another; it shows how they
meet the mind; it analyzes the transition from sense to thought.  The one
describes their nature as apparent to the outward eye; by the other they
are regarded only as the instruments of the mind.  It is in this latter
point of view that we propose to consider them.

The simplest sensation involves an unconscious or nascent operation of the
mind; it implies objects of sense, and objects of sense have differences of
form, number, colour.  But the conception of an object without us, or the
power of discriminating numbers, forms, colours, is not given by the sense,
but by the mind.  A mere sensation does not attain to distinctness:  it is
a confused impression, sugkechumenon ti, as Plato says (Republic), until
number introduces light and order into the confusion.  At what point
confusion becomes distinctness is a question of degree which cannot be
precisely determined.  The distant object, the undefined notion, come out
into relief as we approach them or attend to them.  Or we may assist the
analysis by attempting to imagine the world first dawning upon the eye of
the infant or of a person newly restored to sight.  Yet even with them the
mind as well as the eye opens or enlarges.  For all three are inseparably
bound together--the object would be nowhere and nothing, if not perceived
by the sense, and the sense would have no power of distinguishing without
the mind.

But prior to objects of sense there is a third nature in which they are
contained--that is to say, space, which may be explained in various ways. 
It is the element which surrounds them; it is the vacuum or void which they
leave or occupy when passing from one portion of space to another.  It
might be described in the language of ancient philosophy, as 'the Not-
being' of objects.  It is a negative idea which in the course of ages has
become positive.  It is originally derived from the contemplation of the
world without us--the boundless earth or sea, the vacant heaven, and is
therefore acquired chiefly through the sense of sight:  to the blind the
conception of space is feeble and inadequate, derived for the most part
from touch or from the descriptions of others.  At first it appears to be
continuous; afterwards we perceive it to be capable of division by lines or
points, real or imaginary.  By the help of mathematics we form another idea
of space, which is altogether independent of experience.  Geometry teaches
us that the innumerable lines and figures by which space is or may be
intersected are absolutely true in all their combinations and consequences. 
New and unchangeable properties of space are thus developed, which are
proved to us in a thousand ways by mathematical reasoning as well as by
common experience.  Through quantity and measure we are conducted to our
simplest and purest notion of matter, which is to the cube or solid what
space is to the square or surface.  And all our applications of mathematics
are applications of our ideas of space to matter.  No wonder then that they
seem to have a necessary existence to us.  Being the simplest of our ideas,
space is also the one of which we have the most difficulty in ridding
ourselves.  Neither can we set a limit to it, for wherever we fix a limit,
space is springing up beyond.  Neither can we conceive a smallest or
indivisible portion of it; for within the smallest there is a smaller
still; and even these inconceivable qualities of space, whether the
infinite or the infinitesimal, may be made the subject of reasoning and
have a certain truth to us.

Whether space exists in the mind or out of it, is a question which has no
meaning.  We should rather say that without it the mind is incapable of
conceiving the body, and therefore of conceiving itself.  The mind may be
indeed imagined to contain the body, in the same way that Aristotle (partly
following Plato) supposes God to be the outer heaven or circle of the
universe.  But how can the individual mind carry about the universe of
space packed up within, or how can separate minds have either a universe of
their own or a common universe?  In such conceptions there seems to be a
confusion of the individual and the universal.  To say that we can only
have a true idea of ourselves when we deny the reality of that by which we
have any idea of ourselves is an absurdity.  The earth which is our
habitation and 'the starry heaven above' and we ourselves are equally an
illusion, if space is only a quality or condition of our minds.

Again, we may compare the truths of space with other truths derived from
experience, which seem to have a necessity to us in proportion to the
frequency of their recurrence or the truth of the consequences which may be
inferred from them.  We are thus led to remark that the necessity in our
ideas of space on which much stress has been laid, differs in a slight
degree only from the necessity which appears to belong to other of our
ideas, e.g. weight, motion, and the like.  And there is another way in
which this necessity may be explained.  We have been taught it, and the
truth which we were taught or which we inherited has never been
contradicted in all our experience and is therefore confirmed by it.  Who
can resist an idea which is presented to him in a general form in every
moment of his life and of which he finds no instance to the contrary?  The
greater part of what is sometimes regarded as the a priori intuition of
space is really the conception of the various geometrical figures of which
the properties have been revealed by mathematical analysis.  And the
certainty of these properties is immeasurably increased to us by our
finding that they hold good not only in every instance, but in all the
consequences which are supposed to flow from them.

Neither must we forget that our idea of space, like our other ideas, has a
history.  The Homeric poems contain no word for it; even the later Greek
philosophy has not the Kantian notion of space, but only the definite
'place' or 'the infinite.'  To Plato, in the Timaeus, it is known only as
the 'nurse of generation.'  When therefore we speak of the necessity of our
ideas of space we must remember that this is a necessity which has grown up
with the growth of the human mind, and has been made by ourselves.  We can
free ourselves from the perplexities which are involved in it by ascending
to a time in which they did not as yet exist.  And when space or time are
described as 'a priori forms or intuitions added to the matter given in
sensation,' we should consider that such expressions belong really to the
'pre-historic study' of philosophy, i.e. to the eighteenth century, when
men sought to explain the human mind without regard to history or language
or the social nature of man.

In every act of sense there is a latent perception of space, of which we
only become conscious when objects are withdrawn from it.  There are
various ways in which we may trace the connexion between them.  We may
think of space as unresisting matter, and of matter as divided into
objects; or of objects again as formed by abstraction into a collective
notion of matter, and of matter as rarefied into space.  And motion may be
conceived as the union of there and not there in space, and force as the
materializing or solidification of motion.  Space again is the individual
and universal in one; or, in other words, a perception and also a
conception.  So easily do what are sometimes called our simple ideas pass
into one another, and differences of kind resolve themselves into
differences of degree.

Within or behind space there is another abstraction in many respects
similar to it--time, the form of the inward, as space is the form of the
outward.  As we cannot think of outward objects of sense or of outward
sensations without space, so neither can we think of a succession of
sensations without time.  It is the vacancy of thoughts or sensations, as
space is the void of outward objects, and we can no more imagine the mind
without the one than the world without the other.  It is to arithmetic what
space is to geometry; or, more strictly, arithmetic may be said to be
equally applicable to both.  It is defined in our minds, partly by the
analogy of space and partly by the recollection of events which have
happened to us, or the consciousness of feelings which we are experiencing. 
Like space, it is without limit, for whatever beginning or end of time we
fix, there is a beginning and end before them, and so on without end.  We
speak of a past, present, and future, and again the analogy of space
assists us in conceiving of them as coexistent.  When the limit of time is
removed there arises in our minds the idea of eternity, which at first,
like time itself, is only negative, but gradually, when connected with the
world and the divine nature, like the other negative infinity of space,
becomes positive.  Whether time is prior to the mind and to experience, or
coeval with them, is (like the parallel question about space) unmeaning. 
Like space it has been realized gradually:  in the Homeric poems, or even
in the Hesiodic cosmogony, there is no more notion of time than of space. 
The conception of being is more general than either, and might therefore
with greater plausibility be affirmed to be a condition or quality of the
mind.  The a priori intuitions of Kant would have been as unintelligible to
Plato as his a priori synthetical propositions to Aristotle.  The
philosopher of Konigsberg supposed himself to be analyzing a necessary mode
of thought:  he was not aware that he was dealing with a mere abstraction. 
But now that we are able to trace the gradual developement of ideas through
religion, through language, through abstractions, why should we interpose
the fiction of time between ourselves and realities?  Why should we single
out one of these abstractions to be the a priori condition of all the
others?  It comes last and not first in the order of our thoughts, and is
not the condition precedent of them, but the last generalization of them. 
Nor can any principle be imagined more suicidal to philosophy than to
assume that all the truth which we are capable of attaining is seen only
through an unreal medium.  If all that exists in time is illusion, we may
well ask with Plato, 'What becomes of the mind?'

Leaving the a priori conditions of sensation we may proceed to consider
acts of sense.  These admit of various degrees of duration or intensity;
they admit also of a greater or less extension from one object, which is
perceived directly, to many which are perceived indirectly or in a less
degree, and to the various associations of the object which are latent in
the mind.  In general the greater the intension the less the extension of
them.  The simplest sensation implies some relation of objects to one
another, some position in space, some relation to a previous or subsequent
sensation.  The acts of seeing and hearing may be almost unconscious and
may pass away unnoted; they may also leave an impression behind them or
power of recalling them.  If, after seeing an object we shut our eyes, the
object remains dimly seen in the same or about the same place, but with
form and lineaments half filled up.  This is the simplest act of memory. 
And as we cannot see one thing without at the same time seeing another,
different objects hang together in recollection, and when we call for one
the other quickly follows.  To think of the place in which we have last
seen a thing is often the best way of recalling it to the mind.  Hence
memory is dependent on association.  The act of recollection may be
compared to the sight of an object at a great distance which we have
previously seen near and seek to bring near to us in thought.  Memory is to
sense as dreaming is to waking; and like dreaming has a wayward and
uncertain power of recalling impressions from the past.

Thus begins the passage from the outward to the inward sense.  But as yet
there is no conception of a universal--the mind only remembers the
individual object or objects, and is always attaching to them some colour
or association of sense.  The power of recollection seems to depend on the
intensity or largeness of the perception, or on the strength of some
emotion with which it is inseparably connected.  This is the natural memory
which is allied to sense, such as children appear to have and barbarians
and animals.  It is necessarily limited in range, and its limitation is its
strength.  In later life, when the mind has become crowded with names,
acts, feelings, images innumerable, we acquire by education another memory
of system and arrangement which is both stronger and weaker than the first
--weaker in the recollection of sensible impressions as they are
represented to us by eye or ear--stronger by the natural connexion of ideas
with objects or with one another.  And many of the notions which form a
part of the train of our thoughts are hardly realized by us at the time,
but, like numbers or algebraical symbols, are used as signs only, thus
lightening the labour of recollection.

And now we may suppose that numerous images present themselves to the mind,
which begins to act upon them and to arrange them in various ways.  Besides
the impression of external objects present with us or just absent from us,
we have a dimmer conception of other objects which have disappeared from
our immediate recollection and yet continue to exist in us.  The mind is
full of fancies which are passing to and fro before it.  Some feeling or
association calls them up, and they are uttered by the lips.  This is the
first rudimentary imagination, which may be truly described in the language
of Hobbes, as 'decaying sense,' an expression which may be applied with
equal truth to memory as well.  For memory and imagination, though we
sometimes oppose them, are nearly allied; the difference between them seems
chiefly to lie in the activity of the one compared with the passivity of
the other.  The sense decaying in memory receives a flash of light or life
from imagination.  Dreaming is a link of connexion between them; for in
dreaming we feebly recollect and also feebly imagine at one and the same
time.  When reason is asleep the lower part of the mind wanders at will
amid the images which have been received from without, the intelligent
element retires, and the sensual or sensuous takes its place.  And so in
the first efforts of imagination reason is latent or set aside; and images,
in part disorderly, but also having a unity (however imperfect) of their
own, pour like a flood over the mind.  And if we could penetrate into the
heads of animals we should probably find that their intelligence, or the
state of what in them is analogous to our intelligence, is of this nature.

Thus far we have been speaking of men, rather in the points in which they
resemble animals than in the points in which they differ from them.  The
animal too has memory in various degrees, and the elements of imagination,
if, as appears to be the case, he dreams.  How far their powers or
instincts are educated by the circumstances of their lives or by
intercourse with one another or with mankind, we cannot precisely tell. 
They, like ourselves, have the physical inheritance of form, scent,
hearing, sight, and other qualities or instincts.  But they have not the
mental inheritance of thoughts and ideas handed down by tradition, 'the
slow additions that build up the mind' of the human race.  And language,
which is the great educator of mankind, is wanting in them; whereas in us
language is ever present--even in the infant the latent power of naming is
almost immediately observable.  And therefore the description which has
been already given of the nascent power of the faculties is in reality an
anticipation.  For simultaneous with their growth in man a growth of
language must be supposed.  The child of two years old sees the fire once
and again, and the feeble observation of the same recurring object is
associated with the feeble utterance of the name by which he is taught to
call it.  Soon he learns to utter the name when the object is no longer
there, but the desire or imagination of it is present to him.  At first in
every use of the word there is a colour of sense, an indistinct picture of
the object which accompanies it.  But in later years he sees in the name
only the universal or class word, and the more abstract the notion becomes,
the more vacant is the image which is presented to him.  Henceforward all
the operations of his mind, including the perceptions of sense, are a
synthesis of sensations, words, conceptions.  In seeing or hearing or
looking or listening the sensible impression prevails over the conception
and the word.  In reflection the process is reversed--the outward object
fades away into nothingness, the name or the conception or both together
are everything.  Language, like number, is intermediate between the two,
partaking of the definiteness of the outer and of the universality of the
inner world.  For logic teaches us that every word is really a universal,
and only condescends by the help of position or circumlocution to become
the expression of individuals or particulars.  And sometimes by using words
as symbols we are able to give a 'local habitation and a name' to the
infinite and inconceivable.

Thus we see that no line can be drawn between the powers of sense and of
reflection--they pass imperceptibly into one another.  We may indeed
distinguish between the seeing and the closed eye--between the sensation
and the recollection of it.  But this distinction carries us a very little
way, for recollection is present in sight as well as sight in recollection. 
There is no impression of sense which does not simultaneously recall
differences of form, number, colour, and the like.  Neither is such a
distinction applicable at all to our internal bodily sensations, which give
no sign of themselves when unaccompanied with pain, and even when we are
most conscious of them, have often no assignable place in the human frame. 
Who can divide the nerves or great nervous centres from the mind which uses
them?  Who can separate the pains and pleasures of the mind from the pains
and pleasures of the body?  The words 'inward and outward,' 'active and
passive,' 'mind and body,' are best conceived by us as differences of
degree passing into differences of kind, and at one time and under one
aspect acting in harmony and then again opposed.  They introduce a system
and order into the knowledge of our being; and yet, like many other general
terms, are often in advance of our actual analysis or observation.

According to some writers the inward sense is only the fading away or
imperfect realization of the outward.  But this leaves out of sight one
half of the phenomenon.  For the mind is not only withdrawn from the world
of sense but introduced to a higher world of thought and reflection, in
which, like the outward sense, she is trained and educated.  By use the
outward sense becomes keener and more intense, especially when confined
within narrow limits.  The savage with little or no thought has a quicker
discernment of the track than the civilised man; in like manner the dog,
having the help of scent as well as of sight, is superior to the savage. 
By use again the inward thought becomes more defined and distinct; what was
at first an effort is made easy by the natural instrumentality of language,
and the mind learns to grasp universals with no more exertion than is
required for the sight of an outward object.  There is a natural connexion
and arrangement of them, like the association of objects in a landscape. 
Just as a note or two of music suffices to recall a whole piece to the
musician's or composer's mind, so a great principle or leading thought
suggests and arranges a world of particulars.  The power of reflection is
not feebler than the faculty of sense, but of a higher and more
comprehensive nature.  It not only receives the universals of sense, but
gives them a new content by comparing and combining them with one another. 
It withdraws from the seen that it may dwell in the unseen.  The sense only
presents us with a flat and impenetrable surface:  the mind takes the world
to pieces and puts it together on a new pattern.  The universals which are
detached from sense are reconstructed in science.  They and not the mere
impressions of sense are the truth of the world in which we live; and (as
an argument to those who will only believe 'what they can hold in their
hands') we may further observe that they are the source of our power over
it.  To say that the outward sense is stronger than the inward is like
saying that the arm of the workman is stronger than the constructing or
directing mind.

Returning to the senses we may briefly consider two questions--first their
relation to the mind, secondly, their relation to outward objects:--

1.  The senses are not merely 'holes set in a wooden horse' (Theaet.), but
instruments of the mind with which they are organically connected.  There
is no use of them without some use of words--some natural or latent logic--
some previous experience or observation.  Sensation, like all other mental
processes, is complex and relative, though apparently simple.  The senses
mutually confirm and support one another; it is hard to say how much our
impressions of hearing may be affected by those of sight, or how far our
impressions of sight may be corrected by the touch, especially in infancy. 
The confirmation of them by one another cannot of course be given by any
one of them.  Many intuitions which are inseparable from the act of sense
are really the result of complicated reasonings.  The most cursory glance
at objects enables the experienced eye to judge approximately of their
relations and distance, although nothing is impressed upon the retina
except colour, including gradations of light and shade.  From these
delicate and almost imperceptible differences we seem chiefly to derive our
ideas of distance and position.  By comparison of what is near with what is
distant we learn that the tree, house, river, etc. which are a long way off
are objects of a like nature with those which are seen by us in our
immediate neighbourhood, although the actual impression made on the eye is
very different in one case and in the other.  This is a language of 'large
and small letters' (Republic), slightly differing in form and exquisitely
graduated by distance, which we are learning all our life long, and which
we attain in various degrees according to our powers of sight or
observation.  There is nor the consideration.  The greater or less strain
upon the nerves of the eye or ear is communicated to the mind and silently
informs the judgment.  We have also the use not of one eye only, but of
two, which give us a wider range, and help us to discern, by the greater or
less acuteness of the angle which the rays of sight form, the distance of
an object and its relation to other objects.  But we are already passing
beyond the limits of our actual knowledge on a subject which has given rise
to many conjectures.  More important than the addition of another
conjecture is the observation, whether in the case of sight or of any other
sense, of the great complexity of the causes and the great simplicity of
the effect.

The sympathy of the mind and the ear is no less striking than the sympathy
of the mind and the eye.  Do we not seem to perceive instinctively and as
an act of sense the differences of articulate speech and of musical notes? 
Yet how small a part of speech or of music is produced by the impression of
the ear compared with that which is furnished by the mind!

Again:  the more refined faculty of sense, as in animals so also in man,
seems often to be transmitted by inheritance.  Neither must we forget that
in the use of the senses, as in his whole nature, man is a social being,
who is always being educated by language, habit, and the teaching of other
men as well as by his own observation.  He knows distance because he is
taught it by a more experienced judgment than his own; he distinguishes
sounds because he is told to remark them by a person of a more discerning
ear.  And as we inherit from our parents or other ancestors peculiar powers
of sense or feeling, so we improve and strengthen them, not only by regular
teaching, but also by sympathy and communion with other persons.

2.  The second question, namely, that concerning the relation of the mind
to external objects, is really a trifling one, though it has been made the
subject of a famous philosophy.  We may if we like, with Berkeley, resolve
objects of sense into sensations; but the change is one of name only, and
nothing is gained and something is lost by such a resolution or confusion
of them.  For we have not really made a single step towards idealism, and
any arbitrary inversion of our ordinary modes of speech is disturbing to
the mind.  The youthful metaphysician is delighted at his marvellous
discovery that nothing is, and that what we see or feel is our sensation
only:  for a day or two the world has a new interest to him; he alone knows
the secret which has been communicated to him by the philosopher, that mind
is all--when in fact he is going out of his mind in the first intoxication
of a great thought.  But he soon finds that all things remain as they were
--the laws of motion, the properties of matter, the qualities of
substances.  After having inflicted his theories on any one who is willing
to receive them 'first on his father and mother, secondly on some other
patient listener, thirdly on his dog,' he finds that he only differs from
the rest of mankind in the use of a word.  He had once hoped that by
getting rid of the solidity of matter he might open a passage to worlds
beyond.  He liked to think of the world as the representation of the divine
nature, and delighted to imagine angels and spirits wandering through
space, present in the room in which he is sitting without coming through
the door, nowhere and everywhere at the same instant.  At length he finds
that he has been the victim of his own fancies; he has neither more nor
less evidence of the supernatural than he had before.  He himself has
become unsettled, but the laws of the world remain fixed as at the
beginning.  He has discovered that his appeal to the fallibility of sense
was really an illusion.  For whatever uncertainty there may be in the
appearances of nature, arises only out of the imperfection or variation of
the human senses, or possibly from the deficiency of certain branches of
knowledge; when science is able to apply her tests, the uncertainty is at
an end.  We are apt sometimes to think that moral and metaphysical
philosophy are lowered by the influence which is exercised over them by
physical science.  But any interpretation of nature by physical science is
far in advance of such idealism.  The philosophy of Berkeley, while giving
unbounded license to the imagination, is still grovelling on the level of
sense.

We may, if we please, carry this scepticism a step further, and deny, not
only objects of sense, but the continuity of our sensations themselves.  We
may say with Protagoras and Hume that what is appears, and that what
appears appears only to individuals, and to the same individual only at one
instant.  But then, as Plato asks,--and we must repeat the question,--What
becomes of the mind?  Experience tells us by a thousand proofs that our
sensations of colour, taste, and the like, are the same as they were an
instant ago--that the act which we are performing one minute is continued
by us in the next--and also supplies abundant proof that the perceptions of
other men are, speaking generally, the same or nearly the same with our
own.  After having slowly and laboriously in the course of ages gained a
conception of a whole and parts, of the constitution of the mind, of the
relation of man to God and nature, imperfect indeed, but the best we can,
we are asked to return again to the 'beggarly elements' of ancient
scepticism, and acknowledge only atoms and sensations devoid of life or
unity.  Why should we not go a step further still and doubt the existence
of the senses of all things?  We are but 'such stuff as dreams are made
of;' for we have left ourselves no instruments of thought by which we can
distinguish man from the animals, or conceive of the existence even of a
mollusc.  And observe, this extreme scepticism has been allowed to spring
up among us, not, like the ancient scepticism, in an age when nature and
language really seemed to be full of illusions, but in the eighteenth and
nineteenth centuries, when men walk in the daylight of inductive science.

The attractiveness of such speculations arises out of their true nature not
being perceived.  They are veiled in graceful language; they are not pushed
to extremes; they stop where the human mind is disposed also to stop--short
of a manifest absurdity.  Their inconsistency is not observed by their
authors or by mankind in general, who are equally inconsistent themselves. 
They leave on the mind a pleasing sense of wonder and novelty:  in youth
they seem to have a natural affinity to one class of persons as poetry has
to another; but in later life either we drift back into common sense, or we
make them the starting-points of a higher philosophy.

We are often told that we should enquire into all things before we accept
them;--with what limitations is this true?  For we cannot use our senses
without admitting that we have them, or think without presupposing that
there is in us a power of thought, or affirm that all knowledge is derived
from experience without implying that this first principle of knowledge is
prior to experience.  The truth seems to be that we begin with the natural
use of the mind as of the body, and we seek to describe this as well as we
can.  We eat before we know the nature of digestion; we think before we
know the nature of reflection.  As our knowledge increases, our perception
of the mind enlarges also.  We cannot indeed get beyond facts, but neither
can we draw any line which separates facts from ideas.  And the mind is not
something separate from them but included in them, and they in the mind,
both having a distinctness and individuality of their own.  To reduce our
conception of mind to a succession of feelings and sensations is like the
attempt to view a wide prospect by inches through a microscope, or to
calculate a period of chronology by minutes.  The mind ceases to exist when
it loses its continuity, which though far from being its highest
determination, is yet necessary to any conception of it.  Even an inanimate
nature cannot be adequately represented as an endless succession of states
or conditions.

Paragraph II.  Another division of the subject has yet to be considered: 
Why should the doctrine that knowledge is sensation, in ancient times, or
of sensationalism or materialism in modern times, be allied to the lower
rather than to the higher view of ethical philosophy?  At first sight the
nature and origin of knowledge appear to be wholly disconnected from ethics
and religion, nor can we deny that the ancient Stoics were materialists, or
that the materialist doctrines prevalent in modern times have been
associated with great virtues, or that both religious and philosophical
idealism have not unfrequently parted company with practice.  Still upon
the whole it must be admitted that the higher standard of duty has gone
hand in hand with the higher conception of knowledge.  It is Protagoras who
is seeking to adapt himself to the opinions of the world; it is Plato who
rises above them:  the one maintaining that all knowledge is sensation; the
other basing the virtues on the idea of good.  The reason of this
phenomenon has now to be examined.

By those who rest knowledge immediately upon sense, that explanation of
human action is deemed to be the truest which is nearest to sense.  As
knowledge is reduced to sensation, so virtue is reduced to feeling,
happiness or good to pleasure.  The different virtues--the various
characters which exist in the world--are the disguises of self-interest. 
Human nature is dried up; there is no place left for imagination, or in any
higher sense for religion.  Ideals of a whole, or of a state, or of a law
of duty, or of a divine perfection, are out of place in an Epicurean
philosophy.  The very terms in which they are expressed are suspected of
having no meaning.  Man is to bring himself back as far as he is able to
the condition of a rational beast.  He is to limit himself to the pursuit
of pleasure, but of this he is to make a far-sighted calculation;--he is to
be rationalized, secularized, animalized:  or he is to be an amiable
sceptic, better than his own philosophy, and not falling below the opinions
of the world.

Imagination has been called that 'busy faculty' which is always intruding
upon us in the search after truth.  But imagination is also that higher
power by which we rise above ourselves and the commonplaces of thought and
life.  The philosophical imagination is another name for reason finding an
expression of herself in the outward world.  To deprive life of ideals is
to deprive it of all higher and comprehensive aims and of the power of
imparting and communicating them to others.  For men are taught, not by
those who are on a level with them, but by those who rise above them, who
see the distant hills, who soar into the empyrean.  Like a bird in a cage,
the mind confined to sense is always being brought back from the higher to
the lower, from the wider to the narrower view of human knowledge.  It
seeks to fly but cannot:  instead of aspiring towards perfection, 'it
hovers about this lower world and the earthly nature.'  It loses the
religious sense which more than any other seems to take a man out of
himself.  Weary of asking 'What is truth?' it accepts the 'blind witness of
eyes and ears;' it draws around itself the curtain of the physical world
and is satisfied.  The strength of a sensational philosophy lies in the
ready accommodation of it to the minds of men; many who have been
metaphysicians in their youth, as they advance in years are prone to
acquiesce in things as they are, or rather appear to be.  They are
spectators, not thinkers, and the best philosophy is that which requires of
them the least amount of mental effort.

As a lower philosophy is easier to apprehend than a higher, so a lower way
of life is easier to follow; and therefore such a philosophy seems to
derive a support from the general practice of mankind.  It appeals to
principles which they all know and recognize:  it gives back to them in a
generalized form the results of their own experience.  To the man of the
world they are the quintessence of his own reflections upon life.  To
follow custom, to have no new ideas or opinions, not to be straining after
impossibilities, to enjoy to-day with just so much forethought as is
necessary to provide for the morrow, this is regarded by the greater part
of the world as the natural way of passing through existence.  And many who
have lived thus have attained to a lower kind of happiness or equanimity. 
They have possessed their souls in peace without ever allowing them to
wander into the region of religious or political controversy, and without
any care for the higher interests of man.  But nearly all the good (as well
as some of the evil) which has ever been done in this world has been the
work of another spirit, the work of enthusiasts and idealists, of apostles
and martyrs.  The leaders of mankind have not been of the gentle Epicurean
type; they have personified ideas; they have sometimes also been the
victims of them.  But they have always been seeking after a truth or ideal
of which they fell short; and have died in a manner disappointed of their
hopes that they might lift the human race out of the slough in which they
found them.  They have done little compared with their own visions and
aspirations; but they have done that little, only because they sought to
do, and once perhaps thought that they were doing, a great deal more.

The philosophies of Epicurus or Hume give no adequate or dignified
conception of the mind.  There is no organic unity in a succession of
feeling or sensations; no comprehensiveness in an infinity of separate
actions.  The individual never reflects upon himself as a whole; he can
hardly regard one act or part of his life as the cause or effect of any
other act or part.  Whether in practice or speculation, he is to himself
only in successive instants.  To such thinkers, whether in ancient or in
modern times, the mind is only the poor recipient of impressions--not the
heir of all the ages, or connected with all other minds.  It begins again
with its own modicum of experience having only such vague conceptions of
the wisdom of the past as are inseparable from language and popular
opinion.  It seeks to explain from the experience of the individual what
can only be learned from the history of the world.  It has no conception of
obligation, duty, conscience--these are to the Epicurean or Utilitarian
philosopher only names which interfere with our natural perceptions of
pleasure and pain.

There seem then to be several answers to the question, Why the theory that
all knowledge is sensation is allied to the lower rather than to the higher
view of ethical philosophy:--1st, Because it is easier to understand and
practise; 2ndly, Because it is fatal to the pursuit of ideals, moral,
political, or religious; 3rdly, Because it deprives us of the means and
instruments of higher thought, of any adequate conception of the mind, of
knowledge, of conscience, of moral obligation.

...

ON THE NATURE AND LIMITS Of PSYCHOLOGY.

O gar arche men o me oide, teleute de kai ta metaxu ex ou me oide
sumpeplektai, tis mechane ten toiauten omologian pote epistemen genesthai;
Plato Republic.

Monon gar auto legeiv, osper gumnon kai aperemomenon apo ton onton apanton,
adunaton.  Soph.

Since the above essay first appeared, many books on Psychology have been
given to the world, partly based upon the views of Herbart and other German
philosophers, partly independent of them.  The subject has gained in bulk
and extent; whether it has had any true growth is more doubtful.  It begins
to assume the language and claim the authority of a science; but it is only
an hypothesis or outline, which may be filled up in many ways according to
the fancy of individual thinkers.  The basis of it is a precarious one,--
consciousness of ourselves and a somewhat uncertain observation of the rest
of mankind.  Its relations to other sciences are not yet determined:  they
seem to be almost too complicated to be ascertained.  It may be compared to
an irregular building, run up hastily and not likely to last, because its
foundations are weak, and in many places rest only on the surface of the
ground.  It has sought rather to put together scattered observations and to
make them into a system than to describe or prove them.  It has never
severely drawn the line between facts and opinions.  It has substituted a
technical phraseology for the common use of language, being neither able to
win acceptance for the one nor to get rid of the other.

The system which has thus arisen appears to be a kind of metaphysic
narrowed to the point of view of the individual mind, through which, as
through some new optical instrument limiting the sphere of vision, the
interior of thought and sensation is examined.  But the individual mind in
the abstract, as distinct from the mind of a particular individual and
separated from the environment of circumstances, is a fiction only.  Yet
facts which are partly true gather around this fiction and are naturally
described by the help of it.  There is also a common type of the mind which
is derived from the comparison of many minds with one another and with our
own.  The phenomena of which Psychology treats are familiar to us, but they
are for the most part indefinite; they relate to a something inside the
body, which seems also to overleap the limits of space.  The operations of
this something, when isolated, cannot be analyzed by us or subjected to
observation and experiment.  And there is another point to be considered. 
The mind, when thinking, cannot survey that part of itself which is used in
thought.  It can only be contemplated in the past, that is to say, in the
history of the individual or of the world.  This is the scientific method
of studying the mind.  But Psychology has also some other supports,
specious rather than real.  It is partly sustained by the false analogy of
Physical Science and has great expectations from its near relationship to
Physiology.  We truly remark that there is an infinite complexity of the
body corresponding to the infinite subtlety of the mind; we are conscious
that they are very nearly connected.  But in endeavouring to trace the
nature of the connexion we are baffled and disappointed.  In our knowledge
of them the gulf remains the same:  no microscope has ever seen into
thought; no reflection on ourselves has supplied the missing link between
mind and matter...These are the conditions of this very inexact science,
and we shall only know less of it by pretending to know more, or by
assigning to it a form or style to which it has not yet attained and is not
really entitled.

Experience shows that any system, however baseless and ineffectual, in our
own or in any other age, may be accepted and continue to be studied, if it
seeks to satisfy some unanswered question or is based upon some ancient
tradition, especially if it takes the form and uses the language of
inductive philosophy.  The fact therefore that such a science exists and is
popular, affords no evidence of its truth or value.  Many who have pursued
it far into detail have never examined the foundations on which it rests. 
The have been many imaginary subjects of knowledge of which enthusiastic
persons have made a lifelong study, without ever asking themselves what is
the evidence for them, what is the use of them, how long they will last? 
They may pass away, like the authors of them, and 'leave not a wrack
behind;' or they may survive in fragments.  Nor is it only in the Middle
Ages, or in the literary desert of China or of India, that such systems
have arisen; in our own enlightened age, growing up by the side of Physics,
Ethics, and other really progressive sciences, there is a weary waste of
knowledge, falsely so-called.  There are sham sciences which no logic has
ever put to the test, in which the desire for knowledge invents the
materials of it.

And therefore it is expedient once more to review the bases of Psychology,
lest we should be imposed upon by its pretensions.  The study of it may
have done good service by awakening us to the sense of inveterate errors
familiarized by language, yet it may have fallen into still greater ones;
under the pretence of new investigations it may be wasting the lives of
those who are engaged in it.  It may also be found that the discussion of
it will throw light upon some points in the Theaetetus of Plato,--the
oldest work on Psychology which has come down to us.  The imaginary science
may be called, in the language of ancient philosophy, 'a shadow of a part
of Dialectic or Metaphysic' (Gorg.).

In this postscript or appendix we propose to treat, first, of the true
bases of Psychology; secondly, of the errors into which the students of it
are most likely to fall; thirdly, of the principal subjects which are
usually comprehended under it; fourthly, of the form which facts relating
to the mind most naturally assume.

We may preface the enquiry by two or three remarks:--

(1) We do not claim for the popular Psychology the position of a science at
all; it cannot, like the Physical Sciences, proceed by the Inductive
Method:  it has not the necessity of Mathematics:  it does not, like
Metaphysic, argue from abstract notions or from internal coherence.  It is
made up of scattered observations.  A few of these, though they may
sometimes appear to be truisms, are of the greatest value, and free from
all doubt.  We are conscious of them in ourselves; we observe them working
in others; we are assured of them at all times.  For example, we are
absolutely certain, (a) of the influence exerted by the mind over the body
or by the body over the mind:  (b) of the power of association, by which
the appearance of some person or the occurrence of some event recalls to
mind, not always but often, other persons and events:  (c) of the effect of
habit, which is strongest when least disturbed by reflection, and is to the
mind what the bones are to the body:  (d) of the real, though not
unlimited, freedom of the human will:  (e) of the reference, more or less
distinct, of our sensations, feelings, thoughts, actions, to ourselves,
which is called consciousness, or, when in excess, self-consciousness:  (f)
of the distinction of the 'I' and 'Not I,' of ourselves and outward
objects.  But when we attempt to gather up these elements in a single
system, we discover that the links by which we combine them are apt to be
mere words.  We are in a country which has never been cleared or surveyed;
here and there only does a gleam of light come through the darkness of the
forest.

(2) These fragments, although they can never become science in the ordinary
sense of the word, are a real part of knowledge and may be of great value
in education.  We may be able to add a good deal to them from our own
experience, and we may verify them by it.  Self-examination is one of those
studies which a man can pursue alone, by attention to himself and the
processes of his individual mind.  He may learn much about his own
character and about the character of others, if he will 'make his mind sit
down' and look at itself in the glass.  The great, if not the only use of
such a study is a practical one,--to know, first, human nature, and,
secondly, our own nature, as it truly is.

(3) Hence it is important that we should conceive of the mind in the
noblest and simplest manner.  While acknowledging that language has been
the greatest factor in the formation of human thought, we must endeavour to
get rid of the disguises, oppositions, contradictions, which arise out of
it.  We must disengage ourselves from the ideas which the customary use of
words has implanted in us.  To avoid error as much as possible when we are
speaking of things unseen, the principal terms which we use should be few,
and we should not allow ourselves to be enslaved by them.  Instead of
seeking to frame a technical language, we should vary our forms of speech,
lest they should degenerate into formulas.  A difficult philosophical
problem is better understood when translated into the vernacular.

I.a.  Psychology is inseparable from language, and early language contains
the first impressions or the oldest experience of man respecting himself. 
These impressions are not accurate representations of the truth; they are
the reflections of a rudimentary age of philosophy.  The first and simplest
forms of thought are rooted so deep in human nature that they can never be
got rid of; but they have been perpetually enlarged and elevated, and the
use of many words has been transferred from the body to the mind.  The
spiritual and intellectual have thus become separated from the material--
there is a cleft between them; and the heart and the conscience of man rise
above the dominion of the appetites and create a new language in which they
too find expression.  As the differences of actions begin to be perceived,
more and more names are needed.  This is the first analysis of the human
mind; having a general foundation in popular experience, it is moulded to a
certain extent by hierophants and philosophers.  (See Introd. to Cratylus.)

b.  This primitive psychology is continually receiving additions from the
first thinkers, who in return take a colour from the popular language of
the time.  The mind is regarded from new points of view, and becomes
adapted to new conditions of knowledge.  It seeks to isolate itself from
matter and sense, and to assert its independence in thought.  It recognizes
that it is independent of the external world.  It has five or six natural
states or stages:--(1) sensation, in which it is almost latent or
quiescent:  (2) feeling, or inner sense, when the mind is just awakening: 
(3) memory, which is decaying sense, and from time to time, as with a spark
or flash, has the power of recollecting or reanimating the buried past: 
(4) thought, in which images pass into abstract notions or are intermingled
with them:  (5) action, in which the mind moves forward, of itself, or
under the impulse of want or desire or pain, to attain or avoid some end or
consequence:  and (6) there is the composition of these or the admixture or
assimilation of them in various degrees.  We never see these processes of
the mind, nor can we tell the causes of them.  But we know them by their
results, and learn from other men that so far as we can describe to them or
they to us the workings of the mind, their experience is the same or nearly
the same with our own.

c.  But the knowledge of the mind is not to any great extent derived from
the observation of the individual by himself.  It is the growing
consciousness of the human race, embodied in language, acknowledged by
experience, and corrected from time to time by the influence of literature
and philosophy.  A great, perhaps the most important, part of it is to be
found in early Greek thought.  In the Theaetetus of Plato it has not yet
become fixed:  we are still stumbling on the threshold.  In Aristotle the
process is more nearly completed, and has gained innumerable abstractions,
of which many have had to be thrown away because relative only to the
controversies of the time.  In the interval between Thales and Aristotle
were realized the distinctions of mind and body, of universal and
particular, of infinite and infinitesimal, of idea and phenomenon; the
class conceptions of faculties and virtues, the antagonism of the appetites
and the reason; and connected with this, at a higher stage of development,
the opposition of moral and intellectual virtue; also the primitive
conceptions of unity, being, rest, motion, and the like.  These divisions
were not really scientific, but rather based on popular experience. They
were not held with the precision of modern thinkers, but taken all together
they gave a new existence to the mind in thought, and greatly enlarged and
more accurately defined man's knowledge of himself and of the world.  The
majority of them have been accepted by Christian and Western nations.  Yet
in modern times we have also drifted so far away from Aristotle, that if we
were to frame a system on his lines we should be at war with ordinary
language and untrue to our own consciousness.  And there have been a few
both in mediaeval times and since the Reformation who have rebelled against
the Aristotelian point of view.  Of these eccentric thinkers there have
been various types, but they have all a family likeness.  According to
them, there has been too much analysis and too little synthesis, too much
division of the mind into parts and too little conception of it as a whole
or in its relation to God and the laws of the universe.  They have thought
that the elements of plurality and unity have not been duly adjusted.  The
tendency of such writers has been to allow the personality of man to be
absorbed in the universal, or in the divine nature, and to deny the
distinction between matter and mind, or to substitute one for the other. 
They have broken some of the idols of Psychology:  they have challenged the
received meaning of words:  they have regarded the mind under many points
of view.  But though they may have shaken the old, they have not
established the new; their views of philosophy, which seem like the echo of
some voice from the East, have been alien to the mind of Europe.

d.  The Psychology which is found in common language is in some degree
verified by experience, but not in such a manner as to give it the
character of an exact science.  We cannot say that words always correspond
to facts.  Common language represents the mind from different and even
opposite points of view, which cannot be all of them equally true (compare
Cratylus).  Yet from diversity of statements and opinions may be obtained a
nearer approach to the truth than is to be gained from any one of them.  It
also tends to correct itself, because it is gradually brought nearer to the
common sense of mankind.  There are some leading categories or
classifications of thought, which, though unverified, must always remain
the elements from which the science or study of the mind proceeds.  For
example, we must assume ideas before we can analyze them, and also a
continuing mind to which they belong; the resolution of it into successive
moments, which would say, with Protagoras, that the man is not the same
person which he was a minute ago, is, as Plato implies in the Theaetetus,
an absurdity.

e.  The growth of the mind, which may be traced in the histories of
religions and philosophies and in the thoughts of nations, is one of the
deepest and noblest modes of studying it.  Here we are dealing with the
reality, with the greater and, as it may be termed, the most sacred part of
history.  We study the mind of man as it begins to be inspired by a human
or divine reason, as it is modified by circumstances, as it is distributed
in nations, as it is renovated by great movements, which go beyond the
limits of nations and affect human society on a scale still greater, as it
is created or renewed by great minds, who, looking down from above, have a
wider and more comprehensive vision.  This is an ambitious study, of which
most of us rather 'entertain conjecture' than arrive at any detailed or
accurate knowledge.  Later arises the reflection how these great ideas or
movements of the world have been appropriated by the multitude and found a
way to the minds of individuals.  The real Psychology is that which shows
how the increasing knowledge of nature and the increasing experience of
life have always been slowly transforming the mind, how religions too have
been modified in the course of ages 'that God may be all and in all.'  E
pollaplasion, eoe, to ergon e os nun zeteitai prostatteis.

f.  Lastly, though we speak of the study of mind in a special sense, it may
also be said that there is no science which does not contribute to our
knowledge of it.  The methods of science and their analogies are new
faculties, discovered by the few and imparted to the many.  They are to the
mind, what the senses are to the body; or better, they may be compared to
instruments such as the telescope or microscope by which the discriminating
power of the senses, or to other mechanical inventions, by which the
strength and skill of the human body is so immeasurably increased.

II.  The new Psychology, whatever may be its claim to the authority of a
science, has called attention to many facts and corrected many errors,
which without it would have been unexamined.  Yet it is also itself very
liable to illusion.  The evidence on which it rests is vague and
indefinite.  The field of consciousness is never seen by us as a whole, but
only at particular points, which are always changing.  The veil of language
intercepts facts.  Hence it is desirable that in making an approach to the
study we should consider at the outset what are the kinds of error which
most easily affect it, and note the differences which separate it from
other branches of knowledge.

a.  First, we observe the mind by the mind.  It would seem therefore that
we are always in danger of leaving out the half of that which is the
subject of our enquiry.  We come at once upon the difficulty of what is the
meaning of the word.  Does it differ as subject and object in the same
manner?  Can we suppose one set of feelings or one part of the mind to
interpret another?  Is the introspecting thought the same with the thought
which is introspected?  Has the mind the power of surveying its whole
domain at one and the same time?--No more than the eye can take in the
whole human body at a glance.  Yet there may be a glimpse round the corner,
or a thought transferred in a moment from one point of view to another,
which enables us to see nearly the whole, if not at once, at any rate in
succession.  Such glimpses will hardly enable us to contemplate from within
the mind in its true proportions.  Hence the firmer ground of Psychology is
not the consciousness of inward feelings but the observation of external
actions, being the actions not only of ourselves, but of the innumerable
persons whom we come across in life.

b.  The error of supposing partial or occasional explanation of mental
phenomena to be the only or complete ones.  For example, we are disinclined
to admit of the spontaneity or discontinuity of the mind--it seems to us
like an effect without a cause, and therefore we suppose the train of our
thoughts to be always called up by association.  Yet it is probable, or
indeed certain, that of many mental phenomena there are no mental
antecedents, but only bodily ones.

c.  The false influence of language.  We are apt to suppose that when there
are two or more words describing faculties or processes of the mind, there
are real differences corresponding to them.  But this is not the case.  Nor
can we determine how far they do or do not exist, or by what degree or kind
of difference they are distinguished.  The same remark may be made about
figures of speech.  They fill up the vacancy of knowledge; they are to the
mind what too much colour is to the eye; but the truth is rather concealed
than revealed by them.

d.  The uncertain meaning of terms, such as Consciousness, Conscience,
Will, Law, Knowledge, Internal and External Sense; these, in the language
of Plato, 'we shamelessly use, without ever having taken the pains to
analyze them.'

e.  A science such as Psychology is not merely an hypothesis, but an
hypothesis which, unlike the hypotheses of Physics, can never be verified. 
It rests only on the general impressions of mankind, and there is little or
no hope of adding in any considerable degree to our stock of mental facts.

f.  The parallelism of the Physical Sciences, which leads us to analyze the
mind on the analogy of the body, and so to reduce mental operations to the
level of bodily ones, or to confound one with the other.

g.  That the progress of Physiology may throw a new light on Psychology is
a dream in which scientific men are always tempted to indulge.  But however
certain we may be of the connexion between mind and body, the explanation
of the one by the other is a hidden place of nature which has hitherto been
investigated with little or no success.

h.  The impossibility of distinguishing between mind and body.  Neither in
thought nor in experience can we separate them.  They seem to act together;
yet we feel that we are sometimes under the dominion of the one, sometimes
of the other, and sometimes, both in the common use of language and in
fact, they transform themselves, the one into the good principle, the other
into the evil principle; and then again the 'I' comes in and mediates
between them.  It is also difficult to distinguish outward facts from the
ideas of them in the mind, or to separate the external stimulus to a
sensation from the activity of the organ, or this from the invisible
agencies by which it reaches the mind, or any process of sense from its
mental antecedent, or any mental energy from its nervous expression.

i.  The fact that mental divisions tend to run into one another, and that
in speaking of the mind we cannot always distinguish differences of kind
from differences of degree; nor have we any measure of the strength and
intensity of our ideas or feelings.

j.  Although heredity has been always known to the ancients as well as
ourselves to exercise a considerable influence on human character, yet we
are unable to calculate what proportion this birth-influence bears to
nurture and education.  But this is the real question.  We cannot pursue
the mind into embryology:  we can only trace how, after birth, it begins to
grow.  But how much is due to the soil, how much to the original latent
seed, it is impossible to distinguish.  And because we are certain that
heredity exercises a considerable, but undefined influence, we must not
increase the wonder by exaggerating it.

k.  The love of system is always tending to prevail over the historical
investigation of the mind, which is our chief means of knowing it.  It
equally tends to hinder the other great source of our knowledge of the
mind, the observation of its workings and processes which we can make for
ourselves.

l.  The mind, when studied through the individual, is apt to be isolated--
this is due to the very form of the enquiry; whereas, in truth, it is
indistinguishable from circumstances, the very language which it uses being
the result of the instincts of long-forgotten generations, and every word
which a man utters being the answer to some other word spoken or suggested
by somebody else.

III.  The tendency of the preceding remarks has been to show that
Psychology is necessarily a fragment, and is not and cannot be a connected
system.  We cannot define or limit the mind, but we can describe it.  We
can collect information about it; we can enumerate the principal subjects
which are included in the study of it.  Thus we are able to rehabilitate
Psychology to some extent, not as a branch of science, but as a collection
of facts bearing on human life, as a part of the history of philosophy, as
an aspect of Metaphysic.  It is a fragment of a science only, which in all
probability can never make any great progress or attain to much clearness
or exactness.  It is however a kind of knowledge which has a great interest
for us and is always present to us, and of which we carry about the
materials in our own bosoms.  We can observe our minds and we can
experiment upon them, and the knowledge thus acquired is not easily
forgotten, and is a help to us in study as well as in conduct.

The principal subjects of Psychology may be summed up as follows:--

a.  The relation of man to the world around him,--in what sense and within
what limits can he withdraw from its laws or assert himself against them
(Freedom and Necessity), and what is that which we suppose to be thus
independent and which we call ourselves?  How does the inward differ from
the outward and what is the relation between them, and where do we draw the
line by which we separate mind from matter, the soul from the body?  Is the
mind active or passive, or partly both?  Are its movements identical with
those of the body, or only preconcerted and coincident with them, or is one
simply an aspect of the other?

b.  What are we to think of time and space?  Time seems to have a nearer
connexion with the mind, space with the body; yet time, as well as space,
is necessary to our idea of either.  We see also that they have an analogy
with one another, and that in Mathematics they often interpenetrate.  Space
or place has been said by Kant to be the form of the outward, time of the
inward sense.  He regards them as parts or forms of the mind.  But this is
an unfortunate and inexpressive way of describing their relation to us. 
For of all the phenomena present to the human mind they seem to have most
the character of objective existence.  There is no use in asking what is
beyond or behind them; we cannot get rid of them.  And to throw the laws of
external nature which to us are the type of the immutable into the
subjective side of the antithesis seems to be equally inappropriate.

c.  When in imagination we enter into the closet of the mind and withdraw
ourselves from the external world, we seem to find there more or less
distinct processes which may be described by the words, 'I perceive,' 'I
feel,' 'I think,' 'I want,' 'I wish,' 'I like,' 'I dislike,' 'I fear,' 'I
know,' 'I remember,' 'I imagine,' 'I dream,' 'I act,' 'I endeavour,' 'I
hope.'  These processes would seem to have the same notions attached to
them in the minds of all educated persons.  They are distinguished from one
another in thought, but they intermingle.  It is possible to reflect upon
them or to become conscious of them in a greater or less degree, or with a
greater or less continuity or attention, and thus arise the intermittent
phenomena of consciousness or self-consciousness.  The use of all of them
is possible to us at all times; and therefore in any operation of the mind
the whole are latent.  But we are able to characterise them sufficiently by
that part of the complex action which is the most prominent.  We have no
difficulty in distinguishing an act of sight or an act of will from an act
of thought, although thought is present in both of them.  Hence the
conception of different faculties or different virtues is precarious,
because each of them is passing into the other, and they are all one in the
mind itself; they appear and reappear, and may all be regarded as the ever-
varying phases or aspects or differences of the same mind or person.

d.  Nearest the sense in the scale of the intellectual faculties is memory,
which is a mode rather than a faculty of the mind, and accompanies all
mental operations.  There are two principal kinds of it, recollection and
recognition,--recollection in which forgotten things are recalled or return
to the mind, recognition in which the mind finds itself again among things
once familiar.  The simplest way in which we can represent the former to
ourselves is by shutting our eyes and trying to recall in what we term the
mind's eye the picture of the surrounding scene, or by laying down the book
which we are reading and recapitulating what we can remember of it.  But
many times more powerful than recollection is recognition, perhaps because
it is more assisted by association.  We have known and forgotten, and after
a long interval the thing which we have seen once is seen again by us, but
with a different feeling, and comes back to us, not as new knowledge, but
as a thing to which we ourselves impart a notion already present to us; in
Plato's words, we set the stamp upon the wax.  Every one is aware of the
difference between the first and second sight of a place, between a scene
clothed with associations or bare and divested of them.  We say to
ourselves on revisiting a spot after a long interval:  How many things have
happened since I last saw this!  There is probably no impression ever
received by us of which we can venture to say that the vestiges are
altogether lost, or that we might not, under some circumstances, recover
it.  A long-forgotten knowledge may be easily renewed and therefore is very
different from ignorance.  Of the language learnt in childhood not a word
may be remembered, and yet, when a new beginning is made, the old habit
soon returns, the neglected organs come back into use, and the river of
speech finds out the dried-up channel.

e.  'Consciousness' is the most treacherous word which is employed in the
study of the mind, for it is used in many senses, and has rarely, if ever,
been minutely analyzed.  Like memory, it accompanies all mental operations,
but not always continuously, and it exists in various degrees.  It may be
imperceptible or hardly perceptible:  it may be the living sense that our
thoughts, actions, sufferings, are our own.  It is a kind of attention
which we pay to ourselves, and is intermittent rather than continuous.  Its
sphere has been exaggerated.  It is sometimes said to assure us of our
freedom; but this is an illusion:  as there may be a real freedom without
consciousness of it, so there may be a consciousness of freedom without the
reality.  It may be regarded as a higher degree of knowledge when we not
only know but know that we know.  Consciousness is opposed to habit,
inattention, sleep, death.  It may be illustrated by its derivative
conscience, which speaks to men, not only of right and wrong in the
abstract, but of right and wrong actions in reference to themselves and
their circumstances.

f.  Association is another of the ever-present phenomena of the human mind. 
We speak of the laws of association, but this is an expression which is
confusing, for the phenomenon itself is of the most capricious and
uncertain sort.  It may be briefly described as follows.  The simplest case
of association is that of sense.  When we see or hear separately one of two
things, which we have previously seen or heard together, the occurrence of
the one has a tendency to suggest the other.  So the sight or name of a
house may recall to our minds the memory of those who once lived there. 
Like may recall like and everything its opposite.  The parts of a whole,
the terms of a series, objects lying near, words having a customary order
stick together in the mind.  A word may bring back a passage of poetry or a
whole system of philosophy; from one end of the world or from one pole of
knowledge we may travel to the other in an indivisible instant.  The long
train of association by which we pass from one point to the other,
involving every sort of complex relation, so sudden, so accidental, is one
of the greatest wonders of mind...This process however is not always
continuous, but often intermittent:  we can think of things in isolation as
well as in association; we do not mean that they must all hang from one
another.  We can begin again after an interval of rest or vacancy, as a new
train of thought suddenly arises, as, for example, when we wake of a
morning or after violent exercise.  Time, place, the same colour or sound
or smell or taste, will often call up some thought or recollection either
accidentally or naturally associated with them.  But it is equally
noticeable that the new thought may occur to us, we cannot tell how or why,
by the spontaneous action of the mind itself or by the latent influence of
the body.  Both science and poetry are made up of associations or
recollections, but we must observe also that the mind is not wholly
dependent on them, having also the power of origination.

There are other processes of the mind which it is good for us to study when
we are at home and by ourselves,--the manner in which thought passes into
act, the conflict of passion and reason in many stages, the transition from
sensuality to love or sentiment and from earthly love to heavenly, the slow
and silent influence of habit, which little by little changes the nature of
men, the sudden change of the old nature of man into a new one, wrought by
shame or by some other overwhelming impulse.  These are the greater
phenomena of mind, and he who has thought of them for himself will live and
move in a better-ordered world, and will himself be a better-ordered man.

At the other end of the 'globus intellectualis,' nearest, not to earth and
sense, but to heaven and God, is the personality of man, by which he holds
communion with the unseen world.  Somehow, he knows not how, somewhere, he
knows not where, under this higher aspect of his being he grasps the ideas
of God, freedom and immortality; he sees the forms of truth, holiness and
love, and is satisfied with them.  No account of the mind can be complete
which does not admit the reality or the possibility of another life. 
Whether regarded as an ideal or as a fact, the highest part of man's nature
and that in which it seems most nearly to approach the divine, is a
phenomenon which exists, and must therefore be included within the domain
of Psychology.

IV.  We admit that there is no perfect or ideal Psychology.  It is not a
whole in the same sense in which Chemistry, Physiology, or Mathematics are
wholes:  that is to say, it is not a connected unity of knowledge. 
Compared with the wealth of other sciences, it rests upon a small number of
facts; and when we go beyond these, we fall into conjectures and verbal
discussions.  The facts themselves are disjointed; the causes of them run
up into other sciences, and we have no means of tracing them from one to
the other.  Yet it may be true of this, as of other beginnings of
knowledge, that the attempt to put them together has tested the truth of
them, and given a stimulus to the enquiry into them.

Psychology should be natural, not technical.  It should take the form which
is the most intelligible to the common understanding, because it has to do
with common things, which are familiar to us all.  It should aim at no more
than every reflecting man knows or can easily verify for himself.  When
simple and unpretentious, it is least obscured by words, least liable to
fall under the influence of Physiology or Metaphysic.  It should argue, not
from exceptional, but from ordinary phenomena.  It should be careful to
distinguish the higher and the lower elements of human nature, and not
allow one to be veiled in the disguise of the other, lest through the
slippery nature of language we should pass imperceptibly from good to evil,
from nature in the higher to nature in the neutral or lower sense.  It
should assert consistently the unity of the human faculties, the unity of
knowledge, the unity of God and law.  The difference between the will and
the affections and between the reason and the passions should also be
recognized by it.

Its sphere is supposed to be narrowed to the individual soul; but it cannot
be thus separated in fact.  It goes back to the beginnings of things, to
the first growth of language and philosophy, and to the whole science of
man.  There can be no truth or completeness in any study of the mind which
is confined to the individual.  The nature of language, though not the
whole, is perhaps at present the most important element in our knowledge of
it.  It is not impossible that some numerical laws may be found to have a
place in the relations of mind and matter, as in the rest of nature.  The
old Pythagorean fancy that the soul 'is or has in it harmony' may in some
degree be realized.  But the indications of such numerical harmonies are
faint; either the secret of them lies deeper than we can discover, or
nature may have rebelled against the use of them in the composition of men
and animals.  It is with qualitative rather than with quantitative
differences that we are concerned in Psychology.  The facts relating to the
mind which we obtain from Physiology are negative rather than positive. 
They show us, not the processes of mental action, but the conditions of
which when deprived the mind ceases to act.  It would seem as if the time
had not yet arrived when we can hope to add anything of much importance to
our knowledge of the mind from the investigations of the microscope.  The
elements of Psychology can still only be learnt from reflections on
ourselves, which interpret and are also interpreted by our experience of
others.  The history of language, of philosophy, and religion, the great
thoughts or inventions or discoveries which move mankind, furnish the
larger moulds or outlines in which the human mind has been cast.  From
these the individual derives so much as he is able to comprehend or has the
opportunity of learning.


THEAETETUS

by

Plato

Translated by Benjamin Jowett


PERSONS OF THE DIALOGUE:  Socrates, Theodorus, Theaetetus.

Euclid and Terpsion meet in front of Euclid's house in Megara; they enter
the house, and the dialogue is read to them by a servant.


EUCLID:  Have you only just arrived from the country, Terpsion?

TERPSION:  No, I came some time ago:  and I have been in the Agora looking
for you, and wondering that I could not find you.

EUCLID:  But I was not in the city.

TERPSION:  Where then?

EUCLID:  As I was going down to the harbour, I met Theaetetus--he was being
carried up to Athens from the army at Corinth.

TERPSION:  Was he alive or dead?

EUCLID:  He was scarcely alive, for he has been badly wounded; but he was
suffering even more from the sickness which has broken out in the army.

TERPSION:  The dysentery, you mean?

EUCLID:  Yes.

TERPSION:  Alas! what a loss he will be!

EUCLID:  Yes, Terpsion, he is a noble fellow; only to-day I heard some
people highly praising his behaviour in this very battle.

TERPSION:  No wonder; I should rather be surprised at hearing anything else
of him.  But why did he go on, instead of stopping at Megara?

EUCLID:  He wanted to get home:  although I entreated and advised him to
remain, he would not listen to me; so I set him on his way, and turned
back, and then I remembered what Socrates had said of him, and thought how
remarkably this, like all his predictions, had been fulfilled.  I believe
that he had seen him a little before his own death, when Theaetetus was a
youth, and he had a memorable conversation with him, which he repeated to
me when I came to Athens; he was full of admiration of his genius, and said
that he would most certainly be a great man, if he lived.

TERPSION:  The prophecy has certainly been fulfilled; but what was the
conversation? can you tell me?

EUCLID:  No, indeed, not offhand; but I took notes of it as soon as I got
home; these I filled up from memory, writing them out at leisure; and
whenever I went to Athens, I asked Socrates about any point which I had
forgotten, and on my return I made corrections; thus I have nearly the
whole conversation written down.

TERPSION:  I remember--you told me; and I have always been intending to ask
you to show me the writing, but have put off doing so; and now, why should
we not read it through?--having just come from the country, I should
greatly like to rest.

EUCLID:  I too shall be very glad of a rest, for I went with Theaetetus as
far as Erineum.  Let us go in, then, and, while we are reposing, the
servant shall read to us.

TERPSION:  Very good.

EUCLID:  Here is the roll, Terpsion; I may observe that I have introduced
Socrates, not as narrating to me, but as actually conversing with the
persons whom he mentioned--these were, Theodorus the geometrician (of
Cyrene), and Theaetetus.  I have omitted, for the sake of convenience, the
interlocutory words 'I said,' 'I remarked,' which he used when he spoke of
himself, and again, 'he agreed,' or 'disagreed,' in the answer, lest the
repetition of them should be troublesome.

TERPSION:  Quite right, Euclid.

EUCLID:  And now, boy, you may take the roll and read.

EUCLID'S SERVANT READS.

SOCRATES:  If I cared enough about the Cyrenians, Theodorus, I would ask
you whether there are any rising geometricians or philosophers in that part
of the world.  But I am more interested in our own Athenian youth, and I
would rather know who among them are likely to do well.  I observe them as
far as I can myself, and I enquire of any one whom they follow, and I see
that a great many of them follow you, in which they are quite right,
considering your eminence in geometry and in other ways.  Tell me then, if
you have met with any one who is good for anything.

THEODORUS:  Yes, Socrates, I have become acquainted with one very
remarkable Athenian youth, whom I commend to you as well worthy of your
attention.  If he had been a beauty I should have been afraid to praise
him, lest you should suppose that I was in love with him; but he is no
beauty, and you must not be offended if I say that he is very like you; for
he has a snub nose and projecting eyes, although these features are less
marked in him than in you.  Seeing, then, that he has no personal
attractions, I may freely say, that in all my acquaintance, which is very
large, I never knew any one who was his equal in natural gifts:  for he has
a quickness of apprehension which is almost unrivalled, and he is
exceedingly gentle, and also the most courageous of men; there is a union
of qualities in him such as I have never seen in any other, and should
scarcely have thought possible; for those who, like him, have quick and
ready and retentive wits, have generally also quick tempers; they are ships
without ballast, and go darting about, and are mad rather than courageous;
and the steadier sort, when they have to face study, prove stupid and
cannot remember.  Whereas he moves surely and smoothly and successfully in
the path of knowledge and enquiry; and he is full of gentleness, flowing on
silently like a river of oil; at his age, it is wonderful.

SOCRATES:  That is good news; whose son is he?

THEODORUS:  The name of his father I have forgotten, but the youth himself
is the middle one of those who are approaching us; he and his companions
have been anointing themselves in the outer court, and now they seem to
have finished, and are coming towards us.  Look and see whether you know
him.

SOCRATES:  I know the youth, but I do not know his name; he is the son of
Euphronius the Sunian, who was himself an eminent man, and such another as
his son is, according to your account of him; I believe that he left a
considerable fortune.

THEODORUS:  Theaetetus, Socrates, is his name; but I rather think that the
property disappeared in the hands of trustees; notwithstanding which he is
wonderfully liberal.

SOCRATES:  He must be a fine fellow; tell him to come and sit by me.

THEODORUS:  I will.  Come hither, Theaetetus, and sit by Socrates.

SOCRATES:  By all means, Theaetetus, in order that I may see the reflection
of myself in your face, for Theodorus says that we are alike; and yet if
each of us held in his hands a lyre, and he said that they were tuned
alike, should we at once take his word, or should we ask whether he who
said so was or was not a musician?

THEAETETUS:  We should ask.

SOCRATES:  And if we found that he was, we should take his word; and if
not, not?

THEAETETUS:  True.

SOCRATES:  And if this supposed likeness of our faces is a matter of any
interest to us, we should enquire whether he who says that we are alike is
a painter or not?

THEAETETUS:  Certainly we should.

SOCRATES:  And is Theodorus a painter?

THEAETETUS:  I never heard that he was.

SOCRATES:  Is he a geometrician?

THEAETETUS:  Of course he is, Socrates.

SOCRATES:  And is he an astronomer and calculator and musician, and in
general an educated man?

THEAETETUS:  I think so.

SOCRATES:  If, then, he remarks on a similarity in our persons, either by
way of praise or blame, there is no particular reason why we should attend
to him.

THEAETETUS:  I should say not.

SOCRATES:  But if he praises the virtue or wisdom which are the mental
endowments of either of us, then he who hears the praises will naturally
desire to examine him who is praised:  and he again should be willing to
exhibit himself.

THEAETETUS:  Very true, Socrates.

SOCRATES:  Then now is the time, my dear Theaetetus, for me to examine, and
for you to exhibit; since although Theodorus has praised many a citizen and
stranger in my hearing, never did I hear him praise any one as he has been
praising you.

THEAETETUS:  I am glad to hear it, Socrates; but what if he was only in
jest?

SOCRATES:  Nay, Theodorus is not given to jesting; and I cannot allow you
to retract your consent on any such pretence as that.  If you do, he will
have to swear to his words; and we are perfectly sure that no one will be
found to impugn him.  Do not be shy then, but stand to your word.

THEAETETUS:  I suppose I must, if you wish it.

SOCRATES:  In the first place, I should like to ask what you learn of
Theodorus:  something of geometry, perhaps?

THEAETETUS:  Yes.

SOCRATES:  And astronomy and harmony and calculation?

THEAETETUS:  I do my best.

SOCRATES:  Yes, my boy, and so do I; and my desire is to learn of him, or
of anybody who seems to understand these things.  And I get on pretty well
in general; but there is a little difficulty which I want you and the
company to aid me in investigating.  Will you answer me a question:  'Is
not learning growing wiser about that which you learn?'

THEAETETUS:  Of course.

SOCRATES:  And by wisdom the wise are wise?

THEAETETUS:  Yes.

SOCRATES:  And is that different in any way from knowledge?

THEAETETUS:  What?

SOCRATES:  Wisdom; are not men wise in that which they know?

THEAETETUS:  Certainly they are.

SOCRATES:  Then wisdom and knowledge are the same?

THEAETETUS:  Yes.

SOCRATES:  Herein lies the difficulty which I can never solve to my
satisfaction--What is knowledge?  Can we answer that question?  What say
you? which of us will speak first? whoever misses shall sit down, as at a
game of ball, and shall be donkey, as the boys say; he who lasts out his
competitors in the game without missing, shall be our king, and shall have
the right of putting to us any questions which he pleases...Why is there no
reply?  I hope, Theodorus, that I am not betrayed into rudeness by my love
of conversation?  I only want to make us talk and be friendly and sociable.

THEODORUS:  The reverse of rudeness, Socrates:  but I would rather that you
would ask one of the young fellows; for the truth is, that I am unused to
your game of question and answer, and I am too old to learn; the young will
be more suitable, and they will improve more than I shall, for youth is
always able to improve.  And so having made a beginning with Theaetetus, I
would advise you to go on with him and not let him off.

SOCRATES:  Do you hear, Theaetetus, what Theodorus says?  The philosopher,
whom you would not like to disobey, and whose word ought to be a command to
a young man, bids me interrogate you.  Take courage, then, and nobly say
what you think that knowledge is.

THEAETETUS:  Well, Socrates, I will answer as you and he bid me; and if I
make a mistake, you will doubtless correct me.

SOCRATES:  We will, if we can.

THEAETETUS:  Then, I think that the sciences which I learn from Theodorus--
geometry, and those which you just now mentioned--are knowledge; and I
would include the art of the cobbler and other craftsmen; these, each and
all of, them, are knowledge.

SOCRATES:  Too much, Theaetetus, too much; the nobility and liberality of
your nature make you give many and diverse things, when I am asking for one
simple thing.

THEAETETUS:  What do you mean, Socrates?

SOCRATES:  Perhaps nothing.  I will endeavour, however, to explain what I
believe to be my meaning:  When you speak of cobbling, you mean the art or
science of making shoes?

THEAETETUS:  Just so.

SOCRATES:  And when you speak of carpentering, you mean the art of making
wooden implements?

THEAETETUS:  I do.

SOCRATES:  In both cases you define the subject matter of each of the two
arts?

THEAETETUS:  True.

SOCRATES:  But that, Theaetetus, was not the point of my question:  we
wanted to know not the subjects, nor yet the number of the arts or
sciences, for we were not going to count them, but we wanted to know the
nature of knowledge in the abstract.  Am I not right?

THEAETETUS:  Perfectly right.

SOCRATES:  Let me offer an illustration:  Suppose that a person were to ask
about some very trivial and obvious thing--for example, What is clay? and
we were to reply, that there is a clay of potters, there is a clay of oven-
makers, there is a clay of brick-makers; would not the answer be
ridiculous?

THEAETETUS:  Truly.

SOCRATES:  In the first place, there would be an absurdity in assuming that
he who asked the question would understand from our answer the nature of
'clay,' merely because we added 'of the image-makers,' or of any other
workers.  How can a man understand the name of anything, when he does not
know the nature of it?

THEAETETUS:  He cannot.

SOCRATES:  Then he who does not know what science or knowledge is, has no
knowledge of the art or science of making shoes?

THEAETETUS:  None.

SOCRATES:  Nor of any other science?

THEAETETUS:  No.

SOCRATES:  And when a man is asked what science or knowledge is, to give in
answer the name of some art or science is ridiculous; for the question is,
'What is knowledge?' and he replies, 'A knowledge of this or that.'

THEAETETUS:  True.

SOCRATES:  Moreover, he might answer shortly and simply, but he makes an
enormous circuit.  For example, when asked about the clay, he might have
said simply, that clay is moistened earth--what sort of clay is not to the
point.

THEAETETUS:  Yes, Socrates, there is no difficulty as you put the question. 
You mean, if I am not mistaken, something like what occurred to me and to
my friend here, your namesake Socrates, in a recent discussion.

SOCRATES:  What was that, Theaetetus?

THEAETETUS:  Theodorus was writing out for us something about roots, such
as the roots of three or five, showing that they are incommensurable by the
unit:  he selected other examples up to seventeen --there he stopped.  Now
as there are innumerable roots, the notion occurred to us of attempting to
include them all under one name or class.

SOCRATES:  And did you find such a class?

THEAETETUS:  I think that we did; but I should like to have your opinion.

SOCRATES:  Let me hear.

THEAETETUS:  We divided all numbers into two classes:  those which are made
up of equal factors multiplying into one another, which we compared to
square figures and called square or equilateral numbers;--that was one
class.

SOCRATES:  Very good.

THEAETETUS:  The intermediate numbers, such as three and five, and every
other number which is made up of unequal factors, either of a greater
multiplied by a less, or of a less multiplied by a greater, and when
regarded as a figure, is contained in unequal sides;--all these we compared
to oblong figures, and called them oblong numbers.

SOCRATES:  Capital; and what followed?

THEAETETUS:  The lines, or sides, which have for their squares the
equilateral plane numbers, were called by us lengths or magnitudes; and the
lines which are the roots of (or whose squares are equal to) the oblong
numbers, were called powers or roots; the reason of this latter name being,
that they are commensurable with the former [i.e., with the so-called
lengths or magnitudes] not in linear measurement, but in the value of the
superficial content of their squares; and the same about solids.

SOCRATES:  Excellent, my boys; I think that you fully justify the praises
of Theodorus, and that he will not be found guilty of false witness.

THEAETETUS:  But I am unable, Socrates, to give you a similar answer about
knowledge, which is what you appear to want; and therefore Theodorus is a
deceiver after all.

SOCRATES:  Well, but if some one were to praise you for running, and to say
that he never met your equal among boys, and afterwards you were beaten in
a race by a grown-up man, who was a great runner--would the praise be any
the less true?

THEAETETUS:  Certainly not.

SOCRATES:  And is the discovery of the nature of knowledge so small a
matter, as just now said?  Is it not one which would task the powers of men
perfect in every way?

THEAETETUS:  By heaven, they should be the top of all perfection!
 
SOCRATES:  Well, then, be of good cheer; do not say that Theodorus was
mistaken about you, but do your best to ascertain the true nature of
knowledge, as well as of other things.

THEAETETUS:  I am eager enough, Socrates, if that would bring to light the
truth.

SOCRATES:  Come, you made a good beginning just now; let your own answer
about roots be your model, and as you comprehended them all in one class,
try and bring the many sorts of knowledge under one definition.

THEAETETUS:  I can assure you, Socrates, that I have tried very often, when
the report of questions asked by you was brought to me; but I can neither
persuade myself that I have a satisfactory answer to give, nor hear of any
one who answers as you would have him; and I cannot shake off a feeling of
anxiety.

SOCRATES:  These are the pangs of labour, my dear Theaetetus; you have
something within you which you are bringing to the birth.

THEAETETUS:  I do not know, Socrates; I only say what I feel.

SOCRATES:  And have you never heard, simpleton, that I am the son of a
midwife, brave and burly, whose name was Phaenarete?

THEAETETUS:  Yes, I have.

SOCRATES:  And that I myself practise midwifery?

THEAETETUS:  No, never.

SOCRATES:  Let me tell you that I do though, my friend:  but you must not
reveal the secret, as the world in general have not found me out; and
therefore they only say of me, that I am the strangest of mortals and drive
men to their wits' end.  Did you ever hear that too?

THEAETETUS:  Yes.

SOCRATES:  Shall I tell you the reason?

THEAETETUS:  By all means.

SOCRATES:  Bear in mind the whole business of the midwives, and then you
will see my meaning better:--No woman, as you are probably aware, who is
still able to conceive and bear, attends other women, but only those who
are past bearing.

THEAETETUS:  Yes, I know.

SOCRATES:  The reason of this is said to be that Artemis--the goddess of
childbirth--is not a mother, and she honours those who are like herself;
but she could not allow the barren to be midwives, because human nature
cannot know the mystery of an art without experience; and therefore she
assigned this office to those who are too old to bear.

THEAETETUS:  I dare say.

SOCRATES:  And I dare say too, or rather I am absolutely certain, that the
midwives know better than others who is pregnant and who is not?

THEAETETUS:  Very true.

SOCRATES:  And by the use of potions and incantations they are able to
arouse the pangs and to soothe them at will; they can make those bear who
have a difficulty in bearing, and if they think fit they can smother the
embryo in the womb.

THEAETETUS:  They can.

SOCRATES:  Did you ever remark that they are also most cunning matchmakers,
and have a thorough knowledge of what unions are likely to produce a brave
brood?

THEAETETUS:  No, never.

SOCRATES:  Then let me tell you that this is their greatest pride, more
than cutting the umbilical cord.  And if you reflect, you will see that the
same art which cultivates and gathers in the fruits of the earth, will be
most likely to know in what soils the several plants or seeds should be
deposited.

THEAETETUS:  Yes, the same art.

SOCRATES:  And do you suppose that with women the case is otherwise?

THEAETETUS:  I should think not.

SOCRATES:  Certainly not; but midwives are respectable women who have a
character to lose, and they avoid this department of their profession,
because they are afraid of being called procuresses, which is a name given
to those who join together man and woman in an unlawful and unscientific
way; and yet the true midwife is also the true and only matchmaker.

THEAETETUS:  Clearly.

SOCRATES:  Such are the midwives, whose task is a very important one, but
not so important as mine; for women do not bring into the world at one time
real children, and at another time counterfeits which are with difficulty
distinguished from them; if they did, then the discernment of the true and
false birth would be the crowning achievement of the art of midwifery--you
would think so?

THEAETETUS:  Indeed I should.

SOCRATES:  Well, my art of midwifery is in most respects like theirs; but
differs, in that I attend men and not women; and look after their souls
when they are in labour, and not after their bodies:  and the triumph of my
art is in thoroughly examining whether the thought which the mind of the
young man brings forth is a false idol or a noble and true birth.  And like
the midwives, I am barren, and the reproach which is often made against me,
that I ask questions of others and have not the wit to answer them myself,
is very just--the reason is, that the god compels me to be a midwife, but
does not allow me to bring forth.  And therefore I am not myself at all
wise, nor have I anything to show which is the invention or birth of my own
soul, but those who converse with me profit.  Some of them appear dull
enough at first, but afterwards, as our acquaintance ripens, if the god is
gracious to them, they all make astonishing progress; and this in the
opinion of others as well as in their own.  It is quite dear that they
never learned anything from me; the many fine discoveries to which they
cling are of their own making.  But to me and the god they owe their
delivery.  And the proof of my words is, that many of them in their
ignorance, either in their self-conceit despising me, or falling under the
influence of others, have gone away too soon; and have not only lost the
children of whom I had previously delivered them by an ill bringing up, but
have stifled whatever else they had in them by evil communications, being
fonder of lies and shams than of the truth; and they have at last ended by
seeing themselves, as others see them, to be great fools.  Aristeides, the
son of Lysimachus, is one of them, and there are many others.  The truants
often return to me, and beg that I would consort with them again--they are
ready to go to me on their knees--and then, if my familiar allows, which is
not always the case, I receive them, and they begin to grow again.  Dire
are the pangs which my art is able to arouse and to allay in those who
consort with me, just like the pangs of women in childbirth; night and day
they are full of perplexity and travail which is even worse than that of
the women.  So much for them.  And there are others, Theaetetus, who come
to me apparently having nothing in them; and as I know that they have no
need of my art, I coax them into marrying some one, and by the grace of God
I can generally tell who is likely to do them good.  Many of them I have
given away to Prodicus, and many to other inspired sages.  I tell you this
long story, friend Theaetetus, because I suspect, as indeed you seem to
think yourself, that you are in labour--great with some conception.  Come
then to me, who am a midwife's son and myself a midwife, and do your best
to answer the questions which I will ask you.  And if I abstract and expose
your first-born, because I discover upon inspection that the conception
which you have formed is a vain shadow, do not quarrel with me on that
account, as the manner of women is when their first children are taken from
them.  For I have actually known some who were ready to bite me when I
deprived them of a darling folly; they did not perceive that I acted from
goodwill, not knowing that no god is the enemy of man--that was not within
the range of their ideas; neither am I their enemy in all this, but it
would be wrong for me to admit falsehood, or to stifle the truth.  Once
more, then, Theaetetus, I repeat my old question, 'What is knowledge?'--and
do not say that you cannot tell; but quit yourself like a man, and by the
help of God you will be able to tell.

THEAETETUS:  At any rate, Socrates, after such an exhortation I should be
ashamed of not trying to do my best.  Now he who knows perceives what he
knows, and, as far as I can see at present, knowledge is perception.

SOCRATES:  Bravely said, boy; that is the way in which you should express
your opinion.  And now, let us examine together this conception of yours,
and see whether it is a true birth or a mere wind-egg:--You say that
knowledge is perception?

THEAETETUS:  Yes.

SOCRATES:  Well, you have delivered yourself of a very important doctrine
about knowledge; it is indeed the opinion of Protagoras, who has another
way of expressing it.  Man, he says, is the measure of all things, of the
existence of things that are, and of the non-existence of things that are
not:--You have read him?

THEAETETUS:  O yes, again and again.

SOCRATES:  Does he not say that things are to you such as they appear to
you, and to me such as they appear to me, and that you and I are men?

THEAETETUS:  Yes, he says so.

SOCRATES:  A wise man is not likely to talk nonsense.  Let us try to
understand him:  the same wind is blowing, and yet one of us may be cold
and the other not, or one may be slightly and the other very cold?

THEAETETUS:  Quite true.

SOCRATES:  Now is the wind, regarded not in relation to us but absolutely,
cold or not; or are we to say, with Protagoras, that the wind is cold to
him who is cold, and not to him who is not?

THEAETETUS:  I suppose the last.

SOCRATES:  Then it must appear so to each of them?

THEAETETUS:  Yes.

SOCRATES:  And 'appears to him' means the same as 'he perceives.'

THEAETETUS:  True.

SOCRATES:  Then appearing and perceiving coincide in the case of hot and
cold, and in similar instances; for things appear, or may be supposed to
be, to each one such as he perceives them?

THEAETETUS:  Yes.

SOCRATES:  Then perception is always of existence, and being the same as
knowledge is unerring?

THEAETETUS:  Clearly.

SOCRATES:  In the name of the Graces, what an almighty wise man Protagoras
must have been!  He spoke these things in a parable to the common herd,
like you and me, but told the truth, 'his Truth,' (In allusion to a book of
Protagoras' which bore this title.) in secret to his own disciples.

THEAETETUS:  What do you mean, Socrates?

SOCRATES:  I am about to speak of a high argument, in which all things are
said to be relative; you cannot rightly call anything by any name, such as
great or small, heavy or light, for the great will be small and the heavy
light--there is no single thing or quality, but out of motion and change
and admixture all things are becoming relatively to one another, which
'becoming' is by us incorrectly called being, but is really becoming, for
nothing ever is, but all things are becoming.  Summon all philosophers--
Protagoras, Heracleitus, Empedocles, and the rest of them, one after
another, and with the exception of Parmenides they will agree with you in
this.  Summon the great masters of either kind of poetry--Epicharmus, the
prince of Comedy, and Homer of Tragedy; when the latter sings of

'Ocean whence sprang the gods, and mother Tethys,'

does he not mean that all things are the offspring, of flux and motion?

THEAETETUS:  I think so.

SOCRATES:  And who could take up arms against such a great army having
Homer for its general, and not appear ridiculous?  (Compare Cratylus.)

THEAETETUS:  Who indeed, Socrates?

SOCRATES:  Yes, Theaetetus; and there are plenty of other proofs which will
show that motion is the source of what is called being and becoming, and
inactivity of not-being and destruction; for fire and warmth, which are
supposed to be the parent and guardian of all other things, are born of
movement and of friction, which is a kind of motion;--is not this the
origin of fire?

THEAETETUS:  It is.

SOCRATES:  And the race of animals is generated in the same way?

THEAETETUS:  Certainly.

SOCRATES:  And is not the bodily habit spoiled by rest and idleness, but
preserved for a long time by motion and exercise?

THEAETETUS:  True.

SOCRATES:  And what of the mental habit?  Is not the soul informed, and
improved, and preserved by study and attention, which are motions; but when
at rest, which in the soul only means want of attention and study, is
uninformed, and speedily forgets whatever she has learned?

THEAETETUS:  True.

SOCRATES:  Then motion is a good, and rest an evil, to the soul as well as
to the body?

THEAETETUS:  Clearly.

SOCRATES:  I may add, that breathless calm, stillness and the like waste
and impair, while wind and storm preserve; and the palmary argument of all,
which I strongly urge, is the golden chain in Homer, by which he means the
sun, thereby indicating that so long as the sun and the heavens go round in
their orbits, all things human and divine are and are preserved, but if
they were chained up and their motions ceased, then all things would be
destroyed, and, as the saying is, turned upside down.

THEAETETUS:  I believe, Socrates, that you have truly explained his
meaning.

SOCRATES:  Then now apply his doctrine to perception, my good friend, and
first of all to vision; that which you call white colour is not in your
eyes, and is not a distinct thing which exists out of them.  And you must
not assign any place to it:  for if it had position it would be, and be at
rest, and there would be no process of becoming.

THEAETETUS:  Then what is colour?

SOCRATES:  Let us carry the principle which has just been affirmed, that
nothing is self-existent, and then we shall see that white, black, and
every other colour, arises out of the eye meeting the appropriate motion,
and that what we call a colour is in each case neither the active nor the
passive element, but something which passes between them, and is peculiar
to each percipient; are you quite certain that the several colours appear
to a dog or to any animal whatever as they appear to you?

THEAETETUS:  Far from it.

SOCRATES:  Or that anything appears the same to you as to another man?  Are
you so profoundly convinced of this?  Rather would it not be true that it
never appears exactly the same to you, because you are never exactly the
same?

THEAETETUS:  The latter.

SOCRATES:  And if that with which I compare myself in size, or which I
apprehend by touch, were great or white or hot, it could not become
different by mere contact with another unless it actually changed; nor
again, if the comparing or apprehending subject were great or white or hot,
could this, when unchanged from within, become changed by any approximation
or affection of any other thing.  The fact is that in our ordinary way of
speaking we allow ourselves to be driven into most ridiculous and wonderful
contradictions, as Protagoras and all who take his line of argument would
remark.

THEAETETUS:  How? and of what sort do you mean?

SOCRATES:  A little instance will sufficiently explain my meaning:  Here
are six dice, which are more by a half when compared with four, and fewer
by a half than twelve--they are more and also fewer.  How can you or any
one maintain the contrary?

THEAETETUS:  Very true.

SOCRATES:  Well, then, suppose that Protagoras or some one asks whether
anything can become greater or more if not by increasing, how would you
answer him, Theaetetus?

THEAETETUS:  I should say 'No,' Socrates, if I were to speak my mind in
reference to this last question, and if I were not afraid of contradicting
my former answer.

SOCRATES:  Capital! excellent! spoken like an oracle, my boy!  And if you
reply 'Yes,' there will be a case for Euripides; for our tongue will be
unconvinced, but not our mind.  (In allusion to the well-known line of
Euripides, Hippol.: e gloss omomoch e de thren anomotos.)

THEAETETUS:  Very true.

SOCRATES:  The thoroughbred Sophists, who know all that can be known about
the mind, and argue only out of the superfluity of their wits, would have
had a regular sparring-match over this, and would have knocked their
arguments together finely.  But you and I, who have no professional aims,
only desire to see what is the mutual relation of these principles,--
whether they are consistent with each or not.

THEAETETUS:  Yes, that would be my desire.

SOCRATES:  And mine too.  But since this is our feeling, and there is
plenty of time, why should we not calmly and patiently review our own
thoughts, and thoroughly examine and see what these appearances in us
really are?  If I am not mistaken, they will be described by us as
follows:--first, that nothing can become greater or less, either in number
or magnitude, while remaining equal to itself--you would agree?

THEAETETUS:  Yes.

SOCRATES:  Secondly, that without addition or subtraction there is no
increase or diminution of anything, but only equality.

THEAETETUS:  Quite true.

SOCRATES:  Thirdly, that what was not before cannot be afterwards, without
becoming and having become.

THEAETETUS:  Yes, truly.

SOCRATES:  These three axioms, if I am not mistaken, are fighting with one
another in our minds in the case of the dice, or, again, in such a case as
this--if I were to say that I, who am of a certain height and taller than
you, may within a year, without gaining or losing in height, be not so
tall--not that I should have lost, but that you would have increased.  In
such a case, I am afterwards what I once was not, and yet I have not
become; for I could not have become without becoming, neither could I have
become less without losing somewhat of my height; and I could give you ten
thousand examples of similar contradictions, if we admit them at all.  I
believe that you follow me, Theaetetus; for I suspect that you have thought
of these questions before now.

THEAETETUS:  Yes, Socrates, and I am amazed when I think of them; by the
Gods I am! and I want to know what on earth they mean; and there are times
when my head quite swims with the contemplation of them.

SOCRATES:  I see, my dear Theaetetus, that Theodorus had a true insight
into your nature when he said that you were a philosopher, for wonder is
the feeling of a philosopher, and philosophy begins in wonder.  He was not
a bad genealogist who said that Iris (the messenger of heaven) is the child
of Thaumas (wonder).  But do you begin to see what is the explanation of
this perplexity on the hypothesis which we attribute to Protagoras?

THEAETETUS:  Not as yet.

SOCRATES:  Then you will be obliged to me if I help you to unearth the
hidden 'truth' of a famous man or school.

THEAETETUS:  To be sure, I shall be very much obliged.

SOCRATES:  Take a look round, then, and see that none of the uninitiated
are listening.  Now by the uninitiated I mean the people who believe in
nothing but what they can grasp in their hands, and who will not allow that
action or generation or anything invisible can have real existence.

THEAETETUS:  Yes, indeed, Socrates, they are very hard and impenetrable
mortals.

SOCRATES:  Yes, my boy, outer barbarians.  Far more ingenious are the
brethren whose mysteries I am about to reveal to you.  Their first
principle is, that all is motion, and upon this all the affections of which
we were just now speaking are supposed to depend:  there is nothing but
motion, which has two forms, one active and the other passive, both in
endless number; and out of the union and friction of them there is
generated a progeny endless in number, having two forms, sense and the
object of sense, which are ever breaking forth and coming to the birth at
the same moment.  The senses are variously named hearing, seeing, smelling;
there is the sense of heat, cold, pleasure, pain, desire, fear, and many
more which have names, as well as innumerable others which are without
them; each has its kindred object,--each variety of colour has a
corresponding variety of sight, and so with sound and hearing, and with the
rest of the senses and the objects akin to them.  Do you see, Theaetetus,
the bearings of this tale on the preceding argument?

THEAETETUS:  Indeed I do not.

SOCRATES:  Then attend, and I will try to finish the story.  The purport is
that all these things are in motion, as I was saying, and that this motion
is of two kinds, a slower and a quicker; and the slower elements have their
motions in the same place and with reference to things near them, and so
they beget; but what is begotten is swifter, for it is carried to fro, and
moves from place to place.  Apply this to sense:--When the eye and the
appropriate object meet together and give birth to whiteness and the
sensation connatural with it, which could not have been given by either of
them going elsewhere, then, while the sight is flowing from the eye,
whiteness proceeds from the object which combines in producing the colour;
and so the eye is fulfilled with sight, and really sees, and becomes, not
sight, but a seeing eye; and the object which combined to form the colour
is fulfilled with whiteness, and becomes not whiteness but a white thing,
whether wood or stone or whatever the object may be which happens to be
coloured white.  And this is true of all sensible objects, hard, warm, and
the like, which are similarly to be regarded, as I was saying before, not
as having any absolute existence, but as being all of them of whatever kind
generated by motion in their intercourse with one another; for of the agent
and patient, as existing in separation, no trustworthy conception, as they
say, can be formed, for the agent has no existence until united with the
patient, and the patient has no existence until united with the agent; and
that which by uniting with something becomes an agent, by meeting with some
other thing is converted into a patient.  And from all these
considerations, as I said at first, there arises a general reflection, that
there is no one self-existent thing, but everything is becoming and in
relation; and being must be altogether abolished, although from habit and
ignorance we are compelled even in this discussion to retain the use of the
term.  But great philosophers tell us that we are not to allow either the
word 'something,' or 'belonging to something,' or 'to me,' or 'this,' or
'that,' or any other detaining name to be used, in the language of nature
all things are being created and destroyed, coming into being and passing
into new forms; nor can any name fix or detain them; he who attempts to fix
them is easily refuted.  And this should be the way of speaking, not only
of particulars but of aggregates; such aggregates as are expressed in the
word 'man,' or 'stone,' or any name of an animal or of a class.  O
Theaetetus, are not these speculations sweet as honey?  And do you not like
the taste of them in the mouth?

THEAETETUS:  I do not know what to say, Socrates; for, indeed, I cannot
make out whether you are giving your own opinion or only wanting to draw me
out.

SOCRATES:  You forget, my friend, that I neither know, nor profess to know,
anything of these matters; you are the person who is in labour, I am the
barren midwife; and this is why I soothe you, and offer you one good thing
after another, that you may taste them.  And I hope that I may at last help
to bring your own opinion into the light of day:  when this has been
accomplished, then we will determine whether what you have brought forth is
only a wind-egg or a real and genuine birth.  Therefore, keep up your
spirits, and answer like a man what you think.

THEAETETUS:  Ask me.

SOCRATES:  Then once more:  Is it your opinion that nothing is but what
becomes?--the good and the noble, as well as all the other things which we
were just now mentioning?

THEAETETUS:  When I hear you discoursing in this style, I think that there
is a great deal in what you say, and I am very ready to assent.

SOCRATES:  Let us not leave the argument unfinished, then; for there still
remains to be considered an objection which may be raised about dreams and
diseases, in particular about madness, and the various illusions of hearing
and sight, or of other senses.  For you know that in all these cases the
esse-percipi theory appears to be unmistakably refuted, since in dreams and
illusions we certainly have false perceptions; and far from saying that
everything is which appears, we should rather say that nothing is which
appears.

THEAETETUS:  Very true, Socrates.

SOCRATES:  But then, my boy, how can any one contend that knowledge is
perception, or that to every man what appears is?

THEAETETUS:  I am afraid to say, Socrates, that I have nothing to answer,
because you rebuked me just now for making this excuse; but I certainly
cannot undertake to argue that madmen or dreamers think truly, when they
imagine, some of them that they are gods, and others that they can fly, and
are flying in their sleep.

SOCRATES:  Do you see another question which can be raised about these
phenomena, notably about dreaming and waking?

THEAETETUS:  What question?

SOCRATES:  A question which I think that you must often have heard persons
ask:--How can you determine whether at this moment we are sleeping, and all
our thoughts are a dream; or whether we are awake, and talking to one
another in the waking state?

THEAETETUS:  Indeed, Socrates, I do not know how to prove the one any more
than the other, for in both cases the facts precisely correspond;--and
there is no difficulty in supposing that during all this discussion we have
been talking to one another in a dream; and when in a dream we seem to be
narrating dreams, the resemblance of the two states is quite astonishing.

SOCRATES:  You see, then, that a doubt about the reality of sense is easily
raised, since there may even be a doubt whether we are awake or in a dream. 
And as our time is equally divided between sleeping and waking, in either
sphere of existence the soul contends that the thoughts which are present
to our minds at the time are true; and during one half of our lives we
affirm the truth of the one, and, during the other half, of the other; and
are equally confident of both.

THEAETETUS:  Most true.

SOCRATES:  And may not the same be said of madness and other disorders? the
difference is only that the times are not equal.

THEAETETUS:  Certainly.

SOCRATES:  And is truth or falsehood to be determined by duration of time?

THEAETETUS:  That would be in many ways ridiculous.

SOCRATES:  But can you certainly determine by any other means which of
these opinions is true?

THEAETETUS:  I do not think that I can.

SOCRATES:  Listen, then, to a statement of the other side of the argument,
which is made by the champions of appearance.  They would say, as I
imagine--Can that which is wholly other than something, have the same
quality as that from which it differs? and observe, Theaetetus, that the
word 'other' means not 'partially,' but 'wholly other.'

THEAETETUS:  Certainly, putting the question as you do, that which is
wholly other cannot either potentially or in any other way be the same.

SOCRATES:  And must therefore be admitted to be unlike?

THEAETETUS:  True.

SOCRATES:  If, then, anything happens to become like or unlike itself or
another, when it becomes like we call it the same--when unlike, other?

THEAETETUS:  Certainly.

SOCRATES:  Were we not saying that there are agents many and infinite, and
patients many and infinite?

THEAETETUS:  Yes.

SOCRATES:  And also that different combinations will produce results which
are not the same, but different?

THEAETETUS:  Certainly.

SOCRATES:  Let us take you and me, or anything as an example:--There is
Socrates in health, and Socrates sick--Are they like or unlike?

THEAETETUS:  You mean to compare Socrates in health as a whole, and
Socrates in sickness as a whole?

SOCRATES:  Exactly; that is my meaning.

THEAETETUS:  I answer, they are unlike.

SOCRATES:  And if unlike, they are other?

THEAETETUS:  Certainly.

SOCRATES:  And would you not say the same of Socrates sleeping and waking,
or in any of the states which we were mentioning?

THEAETETUS:  I should.

SOCRATES:  All agents have a different patient in Socrates, accordingly as
he is well or ill.

THEAETETUS:  Of course.

SOCRATES:  And I who am the patient, and that which is the agent, will
produce something different in each of the two cases?

THEAETETUS:  Certainly.

SOCRATES:  The wine which I drink when I am in health, appears sweet and
pleasant to me?

THEAETETUS:  True.

SOCRATES:  For, as has been already acknowledged, the patient and agent
meet together and produce sweetness and a perception of sweetness, which
are in simultaneous motion, and the perception which comes from the patient
makes the tongue percipient, and the quality of sweetness which arises out
of and is moving about the wine, makes the wine both to be and to appear
sweet to the healthy tongue.

THEAETETUS:  Certainly; that has been already acknowledged.

SOCRATES:  But when I am sick, the wine really acts upon another and a
different person?

THEAETETUS:  Yes.

SOCRATES:  The combination of the draught of wine, and the Socrates who is
sick, produces quite another result; which is the sensation of bitterness
in the tongue, and the motion and creation of bitterness in and about the
wine, which becomes not bitterness but something bitter; as I myself become
not perception but percipient?

THEAETETUS:  True.

SOCRATES:  There is no other object of which I shall ever have the same
perception, for another object would give another perception, and would
make the percipient other and different; nor can that object which affects
me, meeting another subject, produce the same, or become similar, for that
too would produce another result from another subject, and become
different.

THEAETETUS:  True.

SOCRATES:  Neither can I by myself, have this sensation, nor the object by
itself, this quality.

THEAETETUS:  Certainly not.

SOCRATES:  When I perceive I must become percipient of something--there can
be no such thing as perceiving and perceiving nothing; the object, whether
it become sweet, bitter, or of any other quality, must have relation to a
percipient; nothing can become sweet which is sweet to no one.

THEAETETUS:  Certainly not.

SOCRATES:  Then the inference is, that we (the agent and patient) are or
become in relation to one another; there is a law which binds us one to the
other, but not to any other existence, nor each of us to himself; and
therefore we can only be bound to one another; so that whether a person
says that a thing is or becomes, he must say that it is or becomes to or of
or in relation to something else; but he must not say or allow any one else
to say that anything is or becomes absolutely:--such is our conclusion.

THEAETETUS:  Very true, Socrates.

SOCRATES:  Then, if that which acts upon me has relation to me and to no
other, I and no other am the percipient of it?

THEAETETUS:  Of course.

SOCRATES:  Then my perception is true to me, being inseparable from my own
being; and, as Protagoras says, to myself I am judge of what is and what is
not to me.

THEAETETUS:  I suppose so.

SOCRATES:  How then, if I never err, and if my mind never trips in the
conception of being or becoming, can I fail of knowing that which I
perceive?

THEAETETUS:  You cannot.

SOCRATES:  Then you were quite right in affirming that knowledge is only
perception; and the meaning turns out to be the same, whether with Homer
and Heracleitus, and all that company, you say that all is motion and flux,
or with the great sage Protagoras, that man is the measure of all things;
or with Theaetetus, that, given these premises, perception is knowledge. 
Am I not right, Theaetetus, and is not this your new-born child, of which I
have delivered you?  What say you?

THEAETETUS:  I cannot but agree, Socrates.

SOCRATES:  Then this is the child, however he may turn out, which you and I
have with difficulty brought into the world.  And now that he is born, we
must run round the hearth with him, and see whether he is worth rearing, or
is only a wind-egg and a sham.  Is he to be reared in any case, and not
exposed? or will you bear to see him rejected, and not get into a passion
if I take away your first-born?

THEODORUS:  Theaetetus will not be angry, for he is very good-natured.  But
tell me, Socrates, in heaven's name, is this, after all, not the truth?

SOCRATES:  You, Theodorus, are a lover of theories, and now you innocently
fancy that I am a bag full of them, and can easily pull one out which will
overthrow its predecessor.  But you do not see that in reality none of
these theories come from me; they all come from him who talks with me.  I
only know just enough to extract them from the wisdom of another, and to
receive them in a spirit of fairness.  And now I shall say nothing myself,
but shall endeavour to elicit something from our young friend.

THEODORUS:  Do as you say, Socrates; you are quite right.

SOCRATES:  Shall I tell you, Theodorus, what amazes me in your acquaintance
Protagoras?

THEODORUS:  What is it?

SOCRATES:  I am charmed with his doctrine, that what appears is to each
one, but I wonder that he did not begin his book on Truth with a
declaration that a pig or a dog-faced baboon, or some other yet stranger
monster which has sensation, is the measure of all things; then he might
have shown a magnificent contempt for our opinion of him by informing us at
the outset that while we were reverencing him like a God for his wisdom he
was no better than a tadpole, not to speak of his fellow-men--would not
this have produced an overpowering effect?  For if truth is only sensation,
and no man can discern another's feelings better than he, or has any
superior right to determine whether his opinion is true or false, but each,
as we have several times repeated, is to himself the sole judge, and
everything that he judges is true and right, why, my friend, should
Protagoras be preferred to the place of wisdom and instruction, and deserve
to be well paid, and we poor ignoramuses have to go to him, if each one is
the measure of his own wisdom?  Must he not be talking 'ad captandum' in
all this?  I say nothing of the ridiculous predicament in which my own
midwifery and the whole art of dialectic is placed; for the attempt to
supervise or refute the notions or opinions of others would be a tedious
and enormous piece of folly, if to each man his own are right; and this
must be the case if Protagoras' Truth is the real truth, and the
philosopher is not merely amusing himself by giving oracles out of the
shrine of his book.

THEODORUS:  He was a friend of mine, Socrates, as you were saying, and
therefore I cannot have him refuted by my lips, nor can I oppose you when I
agree with you; please, then, to take Theaetetus again; he seemed to answer
very nicely.

SOCRATES:  If you were to go into a Lacedaemonian palestra, Theodorus,
would you have a right to look on at the naked wrestlers, some of them
making a poor figure, if you did not strip and give them an opportunity of
judging of your own person?

THEODORUS:  Why not, Socrates, if they would allow me, as I think you will,
in consideration of my age and stiffness; let some more supple youth try a
fall with you, and do not drag me into the gymnasium.

SOCRATES:  Your will is my will, Theodorus, as the proverbial philosophers
say, and therefore I will return to the sage Theaetetus:  Tell me,
Theaetetus, in reference to what I was saying, are you not lost in wonder,
like myself, when you find that all of a sudden you are raised to the level
of the wisest of men, or indeed of the gods?--for you would assume the
measure of Protagoras to apply to the gods as well as men?

THEAETETUS:  Certainly I should, and I confess to you that I am lost in
wonder.  At first hearing, I was quite satisfied with the doctrine, that
whatever appears is to each one, but now the face of things has changed.

SOCRATES:  Why, my dear boy, you are young, and therefore your ear is
quickly caught and your mind influenced by popular arguments.  Protagoras,
or some one speaking on his behalf, will doubtless say in reply,--Good
people, young and old, you meet and harangue, and bring in the gods, whose
existence or non-existence I banish from writing and speech, or you talk
about the reason of man being degraded to the level of the brutes, which is
a telling argument with the multitude, but not one word of proof or
demonstration do you offer.  All is probability with you, and yet surely
you and Theodorus had better reflect whether you are disposed to admit of
probability and figures of speech in matters of such importance.  He or any
other mathematician who argued from probabilities and likelihoods in
geometry, would not be worth an ace.

THEAETETUS:  But neither you nor we, Socrates, would be satisfied with such
arguments.

SOCRATES:  Then you and Theodorus mean to say that we must look at the
matter in some other way?

THEAETETUS:  Yes, in quite another way.

SOCRATES:  And the way will be to ask whether perception is or is not the
same as knowledge; for this was the real point of our argument, and with a
view to this we raised (did we not?) those many strange questions.

THEAETETUS:  Certainly.

SOCRATES:  Shall we say that we know every thing which we see and hear? for
example, shall we say that not having learned, we do not hear the language
of foreigners when they speak to us? or shall we say that we not only hear,
but know what they are saying?  Or again, if we see letters which we do not
understand, shall we say that we do not see them? or shall we aver that,
seeing them, we must know them?

THEAETETUS:  We shall say, Socrates, that we know what we actually see and
hear of them--that is to say, we see and know the figure and colour of the
letters, and we hear and know the elevation or depression of the sound of
them; but we do not perceive by sight and hearing, or know, that which
grammarians and interpreters teach about them.

SOCRATES:  Capital, Theaetetus; and about this there shall be no dispute,
because I want you to grow; but there is another difficulty coming, which
you will also have to repulse.

THEAETETUS:  What is it?

SOCRATES:  Some one will say, Can a man who has ever known anything, and
still has and preserves a memory of that which he knows, not know that
which he remembers at the time when he remembers?  I have, I fear, a
tedious way of putting a simple question, which is only, whether a man who
has learned, and remembers, can fail to know?

THEAETETUS:  Impossible, Socrates; the supposition is monstrous.

SOCRATES:  Am I talking nonsense, then?  Think:  is not seeing perceiving,
and is not sight perception?

THEAETETUS:  True.

SOCRATES:  And if our recent definition holds, every man knows that which
he has seen?

THEAETETUS:  Yes.

SOCRATES:  And you would admit that there is such a thing as memory?

THEAETETUS:  Yes.

SOCRATES:  And is memory of something or of nothing?

THEAETETUS:  Of something, surely.

SOCRATES:  Of things learned and perceived, that is?

THEAETETUS:  Certainly.

SOCRATES:  Often a man remembers that which he has seen?

THEAETETUS:  True.

SOCRATES:  And if he closed his eyes, would he forget?

THEAETETUS:  Who, Socrates, would dare to say so?

SOCRATES:  But we must say so, if the previous argument is to be
maintained.

THEAETETUS:  What do you mean?  I am not quite sure that I understand you,
though I have a strong suspicion that you are right.

SOCRATES:  As thus:  he who sees knows, as we say, that which he sees; for
perception and sight and knowledge are admitted to be the same.

THEAETETUS:  Certainly.

SOCRATES:  But he who saw, and has knowledge of that which he saw,
remembers, when he closes his eyes, that which he no longer sees.

THEAETETUS:  True.

SOCRATES:  And seeing is knowing, and therefore not-seeing is not-knowing?

THEAETETUS:  Very true.

SOCRATES:  Then the inference is, that a man may have attained the
knowledge of something, which he may remember and yet not know, because he
does not see; and this has been affirmed by us to be a monstrous
supposition.

THEAETETUS:  Most true.

SOCRATES:  Thus, then, the assertion that knowledge and perception are one,
involves a manifest impossibility?

THEAETETUS:  Yes.

SOCRATES:  Then they must be distinguished?

THEAETETUS:  I suppose that they must.

SOCRATES:  Once more we shall have to begin, and ask 'What is knowledge?'
and yet, Theaetetus, what are we going to do?

THEAETETUS:  About what?

SOCRATES:  Like a good-for-nothing cock, without having won the victory, we
walk away from the argument and crow.

THEAETETUS:  How do you mean?

SOCRATES:  After the manner of disputers (Lys.; Phaedo; Republic), we were
satisfied with mere verbal consistency, and were well pleased if in this
way we could gain an advantage.  Although professing not to be mere
Eristics, but philosophers, I suspect that we have unconsciously fallen
into the error of that ingenious class of persons.

THEAETETUS:  I do not as yet understand you.

SOCRATES:  Then I will try to explain myself:  just now we asked the
question, whether a man who had learned and remembered could fail to know,
and we showed that a person who had seen might remember when he had his
eyes shut and could not see, and then he would at the same time remember
and not know.  But this was an impossibility.  And so the Protagorean fable
came to nought, and yours also, who maintained that knowledge is the same
as perception.

THEAETETUS:  True.

SOCRATES:  And yet, my friend, I rather suspect that the result would have
been different if Protagoras, who was the father of the first of the two
brats, had been alive; he would have had a great deal to say on their
behalf.  But he is dead, and we insult over his orphan child; and even the
guardians whom he left, and of whom our friend Theodorus is one, are
unwilling to give any help, and therefore I suppose that I must take up his
cause myself, and see justice done?

THEODORUS:  Not I, Socrates, but rather Callias, the son of Hipponicus, is
guardian of his orphans.  I was too soon diverted from the abstractions of
dialectic to geometry.  Nevertheless, I shall be grateful to you if you
assist him.

SOCRATES:  Very good, Theodorus; you shall see how I will come to the
rescue.  If a person does not attend to the meaning of terms as they are
commonly used in argument, he may be involved even in greater paradoxes
than these.  Shall I explain this matter to you or to Theaetetus?

THEODORUS:  To both of us, and let the younger answer; he will incur less
disgrace if he is discomfited.

SOCRATES:  Then now let me ask the awful question, which is this:--Can a
man know and also not know that which he knows?

THEODORUS:  How shall we answer, Theaetetus?

THEAETETUS:  He cannot, I should say.

SOCRATES:  He can, if you maintain that seeing is knowing.  When you are
imprisoned in a well, as the saying is, and the self-assured adversary
closes one of your eyes with his hand, and asks whether you can see his
cloak with the eye which he has closed, how will you answer the inevitable
man?

THEAETETUS:  I should answer, 'Not with that eye but with the other.'

SOCRATES:  Then you see and do not see the same thing at the same time.

THEAETETUS:  Yes, in a certain sense.

SOCRATES:  None of that, he will reply; I do not ask or bid you answer in
what sense you know, but only whether you know that which you do not know. 
You have been proved to see that which you do not see; and you have already
admitted that seeing is knowing, and that not-seeing is not-knowing:  I
leave you to draw the inference.

THEAETETUS:  Yes; the inference is the contradictory of my assertion.

SOCRATES:  Yes, my marvel, and there might have been yet worse things in
store for you, if an opponent had gone on to ask whether you can have a
sharp and also a dull knowledge, and whether you can know near, but not at
a distance, or know the same thing with more or less intensity, and so on
without end.  Such questions might have been put to you by a light-armed
mercenary, who argued for pay.  He would have lain in wait for you, and
when you took up the position, that sense is knowledge, he would have made
an assault upon hearing, smelling, and the other senses;--he would have
shown you no mercy; and while you were lost in envy and admiration of his
wisdom, he would have got you into his net, out of which you would not have
escaped until you had come to an understanding about the sum to be paid for
your release.  Well, you ask, and how will Protagoras reinforce his
position?  Shall I answer for him?

THEAETETUS:  By all means.

SOCRATES:  He will repeat all those things which we have been urging on his
behalf, and then he will close with us in disdain, and say:--The worthy
Socrates asked a little boy, whether the same man could remember and not
know the same thing, and the boy said No, because he was frightened, and
could not see what was coming, and then Socrates made fun of poor me.  The
truth is, O slatternly Socrates, that when you ask questions about any
assertion of mine, and the person asked is found tripping, if he has
answered as I should have answered, then I am refuted, but if he answers
something else, then he is refuted and not I.  For do you really suppose
that any one would admit the memory which a man has of an impression which
has passed away to be the same with that which he experienced at the time? 
Assuredly not.  Or would he hesitate to acknowledge that the same man may
know and not know the same thing?  Or, if he is afraid of making this
admission, would he ever grant that one who has become unlike is the same
as before he became unlike?  Or would he admit that a man is one at all,
and not rather many and infinite as the changes which take place in him?  I
speak by the card in order to avoid entanglements of words.  But, O my good
sir, he will say, come to the argument in a more generous spirit; and
either show, if you can, that our sensations are not relative and
individual, or, if you admit them to be so, prove that this does not
involve the consequence that the appearance becomes, or, if you will have
the word, is, to the individual only.  As to your talk about pigs and
baboons, you are yourself behaving like a pig, and you teach your hearers
to make sport of my writings in the same ignorant manner; but this is not
to your credit.  For I declare that the truth is as I have written, and
that each of us is a measure of existence and of non-existence.  Yet one
man may be a thousand times better than another in proportion as different
things are and appear to him.  And I am far from saying that wisdom and the
wise man have no existence; but I say that the wise man is he who makes the
evils which appear and are to a man, into goods which are and appear to
him.  And I would beg you not to press my words in the letter, but to take
the meaning of them as I will explain them.  Remember what has been already
said,--that to the sick man his food appears to be and is bitter, and to
the man in health the opposite of bitter.  Now I cannot conceive that one
of these men can be or ought to be made wiser than the other:  nor can you
assert that the sick man because he has one impression is foolish, and the
healthy man because he has another is wise; but the one state requires to
be changed into the other, the worse into the better.  As in education, a
change of state has to be effected, and the sophist accomplishes by words
the change which the physician works by the aid of drugs.  Not that any one
ever made another think truly, who previously thought falsely.  For no one
can think what is not, or, think anything different from that which he
feels; and this is always true.  But as the inferior habit of mind has
thoughts of kindred nature, so I conceive that a good mind causes men to
have good thoughts; and these which the inexperienced call true, I maintain
to be only better, and not truer than others.  And, O my dear Socrates, I
do not call wise men tadpoles:  far from it; I say that they are the
physicians of the human body, and the husbandmen of plants--for the
husbandmen also take away the evil and disordered sensations of plants, and
infuse into them good and healthy sensations--aye and true ones; and the
wise and good rhetoricians make the good instead of the evil to seem just
to states; for whatever appears to a state to be just and fair, so long as
it is regarded as such, is just and fair to it; but the teacher of wisdom
causes the good to take the place of the evil, both in appearance and in
reality.  And in like manner the Sophist who is able to train his pupils in
this spirit is a wise man, and deserves to be well paid by them.  And so
one man is wiser than another; and no one thinks falsely, and you, whether
you will or not, must endure to be a measure.  On these foundations the
argument stands firm, which you, Socrates, may, if you please, overthrow by
an opposite argument, or if you like you may put questions to me--a method
to which no intelligent person will object, quite the reverse.  But I must
beg you to put fair questions:  for there is great inconsistency in saying
that you have a zeal for virtue, and then always behaving unfairly in
argument.  The unfairness of which I complain is that you do not
distinguish between mere disputation and dialectic:  the disputer may trip
up his opponent as often as he likes, and make fun; but the dialectician
will be in earnest, and only correct his adversary when necessary, telling
him the errors into which he has fallen through his own fault, or that of
the company which he has previously kept.  If you do so, your adversary
will lay the blame of his own confusion and perplexity on himself, and not
on you.  He will follow and love you, and will hate himself, and escape
from himself into philosophy, in order that he may become different from
what he was.  But the other mode of arguing, which is practised by the
many, will have just the opposite effect upon him; and as he grows older,
instead of turning philosopher, he will come to hate philosophy.  I would
recommend you, therefore, as I said before, not to encourage yourself in
this polemical and controversial temper, but to find out, in a friendly and
congenial spirit, what we really mean when we say that all things are in
motion, and that to every individual and state what appears, is.  In this
manner you will consider whether knowledge and sensation are the same or
different, but you will not argue, as you were just now doing, from the
customary use of names and words, which the vulgar pervert in all sorts of
ways, causing infinite perplexity to one another.  Such, Theodorus, is the
very slight help which I am able to offer to your old friend; had he been
living, he would have helped himself in a far more gloriose style.

THEODORUS:  You are jesting, Socrates; indeed, your defence of him has been
most valorous.

SOCRATES:  Thank you, friend; and I hope that you observed Protagoras
bidding us be serious, as the text, 'Man is the measure of all things,' was
a solemn one; and he reproached us with making a boy the medium of
discourse, and said that the boy's timidity was made to tell against his
argument; he also declared that we made a joke of him.

THEODORUS:  How could I fail to observe all that, Socrates?

SOCRATES:  Well, and shall we do as he says?

THEODORUS:  By all means.

SOCRATES:  But if his wishes are to be regarded, you and I must take up the
argument, and in all seriousness, and ask and answer one another, for you
see that the rest of us are nothing but boys.  In no other way can we
escape the imputation, that in our fresh analysis of his thesis we are
making fun with boys.

THEODORUS:  Well, but is not Theaetetus better able to follow a
philosophical enquiry than a great many men who have long beards?

SOCRATES:  Yes, Theodorus, but not better than you; and therefore please
not to imagine that I am to defend by every means in my power your departed
friend; and that you are to defend nothing and nobody.  At any rate, my
good man, do not sheer off until we know whether you are a true measure of
diagrams, or whether all men are equally measures and sufficient for
themselves in astronomy and geometry, and the other branches of knowledge
in which you are supposed to excel them.

THEODORUS:  He who is sitting by you, Socrates, will not easily avoid being
drawn into an argument; and when I said just now that you would excuse me,
and not, like the Lacedaemonians, compel me to strip and fight, I was
talking nonsense--I should rather compare you to Scirrhon, who threw
travellers from the rocks; for the Lacedaemonian rule is 'strip or depart,'
but you seem to go about your work more after the fashion of Antaeus:  you
will not allow any one who approaches you to depart until you have stripped
him, and he has been compelled to try a fall with you in argument.

SOCRATES:  There, Theodorus, you have hit off precisely the nature of my
complaint; but I am even more pugnacious than the giants of old, for I have
met with no end of heroes; many a Heracles, many a Theseus, mighty in
words, has broken my head; nevertheless I am always at this rough exercise,
which inspires me like a passion.  Please, then, to try a fall with me,
whereby you will do yourself good as well as me.

THEODORUS:  I consent; lead me whither you will, for I know that you are
like destiny; no man can escape from any argument which you may weave for
him.  But I am not disposed to go further than you suggest.

SOCRATES:  Once will be enough; and now take particular care that we do not
again unwittingly expose ourselves to the reproach of talking childishly.

THEODORUS:  I will do my best to avoid that error.

SOCRATES:  In the first place, let us return to our old objection, and see
whether we were right in blaming and taking offence at Protagoras on the
ground that he assumed all to be equal and sufficient in wisdom; although
he admitted that there was a better and worse, and that in respect of this,
some who as he said were the wise excelled others.

THEODORUS:  Very true.

SOCRATES:  Had Protagoras been living and answered for himself, instead of
our answering for him, there would have been no need of our reviewing or
reinforcing the argument.  But as he is not here, and some one may accuse
us of speaking without authority on his behalf, had we not better come to a
clearer agreement about his meaning, for a great deal may be at stake?

THEODORUS:  True.

SOCRATES:  Then let us obtain, not through any third person, but from his
own statement and in the fewest words possible, the basis of agreement.

THEODORUS:  In what way?

SOCRATES:  In this way:--His words are, 'What seems to a man, is to him.'

THEODORUS:  Yes, so he says.

SOCRATES:  And are not we, Protagoras, uttering the opinion of man, or
rather of all mankind, when we say that every one thinks himself wiser than
other men in some things, and their inferior in others?  In the hour of
danger, when they are in perils of war, or of the sea, or of sickness, do
they not look up to their commanders as if they were gods, and expect
salvation from them, only because they excel them in knowledge?  Is not the
world full of men in their several employments, who are looking for
teachers and rulers of themselves and of the animals? and there are plenty
who think that they are able to teach and able to rule.  Now, in all this
is implied that ignorance and wisdom exist among them, at least in their
own opinion.

THEODORUS:  Certainly.

SOCRATES:  And wisdom is assumed by them to be true thought, and ignorance
to be false opinion.

THEODORUS:  Exactly.

SOCRATES:  How then, Protagoras, would you have us treat the argument? 
Shall we say that the opinions of men are always true, or sometimes true
and sometimes false?  In either case, the result is the same, and their
opinions are not always true, but sometimes true and sometimes false.  For
tell me, Theodorus, do you suppose that you yourself, or any other follower
of Protagoras, would contend that no one deems another ignorant or mistaken
in his opinion?

THEODORUS:  The thing is incredible, Socrates.

SOCRATES:  And yet that absurdity is necessarily involved in the thesis
which declares man to be the measure of all things.

THEODORUS:  How so?

SOCRATES:  Why, suppose that you determine in your own mind something to be
true, and declare your opinion to me; let us assume, as he argues, that
this is true to you.  Now, if so, you must either say that the rest of us
are not the judges of this opinion or judgment of yours, or that we judge
you always to have a true opinion?  But are there not thousands upon
thousands who, whenever you form a judgment, take up arms against you and
are of an opposite judgment and opinion, deeming that you judge falsely?

THEODORUS:  Yes, indeed, Socrates, thousands and tens of thousands, as
Homer says, who give me a world of trouble.

SOCRATES:  Well, but are we to assert that what you think is true to you
and false to the ten thousand others?

THEODORUS:  No other inference seems to be possible.

SOCRATES:  And how about Protagoras himself?  If neither he nor the
multitude thought, as indeed they do not think, that man is the measure of
all things, must it not follow that the truth of which Protagoras wrote
would be true to no one?  But if you suppose that he himself thought this,
and that the multitude does not agree with him, you must begin by allowing
that in whatever proportion the many are more than one, in that proportion
his truth is more untrue than true.

THEODORUS:  That would follow if the truth is supposed to vary with
individual opinion.

SOCRATES:  And the best of the joke is, that he acknowledges the truth of
their opinion who believe his own opinion to be false; for he admits that
the opinions of all men are true.

THEODORUS:  Certainly.

SOCRATES:  And does he not allow that his own opinion is false, if he
admits that the opinion of those who think him false is true?

THEODORUS:  Of course.

SOCRATES:  Whereas the other side do not admit that they speak falsely?

THEODORUS:  They do not.

SOCRATES:  And he, as may be inferred from his writings, agrees that this
opinion is also true.

THEODORUS:  Clearly.

SOCRATES:  Then all mankind, beginning with Protagoras, will contend, or
rather, I should say that he will allow, when he concedes that his
adversary has a true opinion--Protagoras, I say, will himself allow that
neither a dog nor any ordinary man is the measure of anything which he has
not learned--am I not right?

THEODORUS:  Yes.

SOCRATES:  And the truth of Protagoras being doubted by all, will be true
neither to himself to any one else?

THEODORUS:  I think, Socrates, that we are running my old friend too hard.

SOCRATES:  But I do not know that we are going beyond the truth. 
Doubtless, as he is older, he may be expected to be wiser than we are.  And
if he could only just get his head out of the world below, he would have
overthrown both of us again and again, me for talking nonsense and you for
assenting to me, and have been off and underground in a trice.  But as he
is not within call, we must make the best use of our own faculties, such as
they are, and speak out what appears to us to be true.  And one thing which
no one will deny is, that there are great differences in the understandings
of men.

THEODORUS:  In that opinion I quite agree.

SOCRATES:  And is there not most likely to be firm ground in the
distinction which we were indicating on behalf of Protagoras, viz. that
most things, and all immediate sensations, such as hot, dry, sweet, are
only such as they appear; if however difference of opinion is to be allowed
at all, surely we must allow it in respect of health or disease? for every
woman, child, or living creature has not such a knowledge of what conduces
to health as to enable them to cure themselves.

THEODORUS:  I quite agree.

SOCRATES:  Or again, in politics, while affirming that just and unjust,
honourable and disgraceful, holy and unholy, are in reality to each state
such as the state thinks and makes lawful, and that in determining these
matters no individual or state is wiser than another, still the followers
of Protagoras will not deny that in determining what is or is not expedient
for the community one state is wiser and one counsellor better than
another--they will scarcely venture to maintain, that what a city enacts in
the belief that it is expedient will always be really expedient.  But in
the other case, I mean when they speak of justice and injustice, piety and
impiety, they are confident that in nature these have no existence or
essence of their own--the truth is that which is agreed on at the time of
the agreement, and as long as the agreement lasts; and this is the
philosophy of many who do not altogether go along with Protagoras.  Here
arises a new question, Theodorus, which threatens to be more serious than
the last.

THEODORUS:  Well, Socrates, we have plenty of leisure.

SOCRATES:  That is true, and your remark recalls to my mind an observation
which I have often made, that those who have passed their days in the
pursuit of philosophy are ridiculously at fault when they have to appear
and speak in court.  How natural is this!

THEODORUS:  What do you mean?

SOCRATES:  I mean to say, that those who have been trained in philosophy
and liberal pursuits are as unlike those who from their youth upwards have
been knocking about in the courts and such places, as a freeman is in
breeding unlike a slave.

THEODORUS:  In what is the difference seen?

SOCRATES:  In the leisure spoken of by you, which a freeman can always
command:  he has his talk out in peace, and, like ourselves, he wanders at
will from one subject to another, and from a second to a third,--if the
fancy takes him, he begins again, as we are doing now, caring not whether
his words are many or few; his only aim is to attain the truth.  But the
lawyer is always in a hurry; there is the water of the clepsydra driving
him on, and not allowing him to expatiate at will:  and there is his
adversary standing over him, enforcing his rights; the indictment, which in
their phraseology is termed the affidavit, is recited at the time:  and
from this he must not deviate.  He is a servant, and is continually
disputing about a fellow-servant before his master, who is seated, and has
the cause in his hands; the trial is never about some indifferent matter,
but always concerns himself; and often the race is for his life.  The
consequence has been, that he has become keen and shrewd; he has learned
how to flatter his master in word and indulge him in deed; but his soul is
small and unrighteous.  His condition, which has been that of a slave from
his youth upwards, has deprived him of growth and uprightness and
independence; dangers and fears, which were too much for his truth and
honesty, came upon him in early years, when the tenderness of youth was
unequal to them, and he has been driven into crooked ways; from the first
he has practised deception and retaliation, and has become stunted and
warped.  And so he has passed out of youth into manhood, having no
soundness in him; and is now, as he thinks, a master in wisdom.  Such is
the lawyer, Theodorus.  Will you have the companion picture of the
philosopher, who is of our brotherhood; or shall we return to the argument? 
Do not let us abuse the freedom of digression which we claim.

THEODORUS:  Nay, Socrates, not until we have finished what we are about;
for you truly said that we belong to a brotherhood which is free, and are
not the servants of the argument; but the argument is our servant, and must
wait our leisure.  Who is our judge?  Or where is the spectator having any
right to censure or control us, as he might the poets?

SOCRATES:  Then, as this is your wish, I will describe the leaders; for
there is no use in talking about the inferior sort.  In the first place,
the lords of philosophy have never, from their youth upwards, known their
way to the Agora, or the dicastery, or the council, or any other political
assembly; they neither see nor hear the laws or decrees, as they are
called, of the state written or recited; the eagerness of political
societies in the attainment of offices--clubs, and banquets, and revels,
and singing-maidens,--do not enter even into their dreams.  Whether any
event has turned out well or ill in the city, what disgrace may have
descended to any one from his ancestors, male or female, are matters of
which the philosopher no more knows than he can tell, as they say, how many
pints are contained in the ocean.  Neither is he conscious of his
ignorance.  For he does not hold aloof in order that he may gain a
reputation; but the truth is, that the outer form of him only is in the
city:  his mind, disdaining the littlenesses and nothingnesses of human
things, is 'flying all abroad' as Pindar says, measuring earth and heaven
and the things which are under and on the earth and above the heaven,
interrogating the whole nature of each and all in their entirety, but not
condescending to anything which is within reach.

THEODORUS:  What do you mean, Socrates?

SOCRATES:  I will illustrate my meaning, Theodorus, by the jest which the
clever witty Thracian handmaid is said to have made about Thales, when he
fell into a well as he was looking up at the stars.  She said, that he was
so eager to know what was going on in heaven, that he could not see what
was before his feet.  This is a jest which is equally applicable to all
philosophers.  For the philosopher is wholly unacquainted with his next-
door neighbour; he is ignorant, not only of what he is doing, but he hardly
knows whether he is a man or an animal; he is searching into the essence of
man, and busy in enquiring what belongs to such a nature to do or suffer
different from any other;--I think that you understand me, Theodorus?

THEODORUS:  I do, and what you say is true.

SOCRATES:  And thus, my friend, on every occasion, private as well as
public, as I said at first, when he appears in a law-court, or in any place
in which he has to speak of things which are at his feet and before his
eyes, he is the jest, not only of Thracian handmaids but of the general
herd, tumbling into wells and every sort of disaster through his
inexperience.  His awkwardness is fearful, and gives the impression of
imbecility.  When he is reviled, he has nothing personal to say in answer
to the civilities of his adversaries, for he knows no scandals of any one,
and they do not interest him; and therefore he is laughed at for his
sheepishness; and when others are being praised and glorified, in the
simplicity of his heart he cannot help going into fits of laughter, so that
he seems to be a downright idiot.  When he hears a tyrant or king
eulogized, he fancies that he is listening to the praises of some keeper of
cattle--a swineherd, or shepherd, or perhaps a cowherd, who is
congratulated on the quantity of milk which he squeezes from them; and he
remarks that the creature whom they tend, and out of whom they squeeze the
wealth, is of a less tractable and more insidious nature.  Then, again, he
observes that the great man is of necessity as ill-mannered and uneducated
as any shepherd--for he has no leisure, and he is surrounded by a wall,
which is his mountain-pen.  Hearing of enormous landed proprietors of ten
thousand acres and more, our philosopher deems this to be a trifle, because
he has been accustomed to think of the whole earth; and when they sing the
praises of family, and say that some one is a gentleman because he can show
seven generations of wealthy ancestors, he thinks that their sentiments
only betray a dull and narrow vision in those who utter them, and who are
not educated enough to look at the whole, nor to consider that every man
has had thousands and ten thousands of progenitors, and among them have
been rich and poor, kings and slaves, Hellenes and barbarians, innumerable. 
And when people pride themselves on having a pedigree of twenty-five
ancestors, which goes back to Heracles, the son of Amphitryon, he cannot
understand their poverty of ideas.  Why are they unable to calculate that
Amphitryon had a twenty-fifth ancestor, who might have been anybody, and
was such as fortune made him, and he had a fiftieth, and so on?  He amuses
himself with the notion that they cannot count, and thinks that a little
arithmetic would have got rid of their senseless vanity.  Now, in all these
cases our philosopher is derided by the vulgar, partly because he is
thought to despise them, and also because he is ignorant of what is before
him, and always at a loss.

THEODORUS:  That is very true, Socrates.

SOCRATES:  But, O my friend, when he draws the other into upper air, and
gets him out of his pleas and rejoinders into the contemplation of justice
and injustice in their own nature and in their difference from one another
and from all other things; or from the commonplaces about the happiness of
a king or of a rich man to the consideration of government, and of human
happiness and misery in general--what they are, and how a man is to attain
the one and avoid the other--when that narrow, keen, little legal mind is
called to account about all this, he gives the philosopher his revenge; for
dizzied by the height at which he is hanging, whence he looks down into
space, which is a strange experience to him, he being dismayed, and lost,
and stammering broken words, is laughed at, not by Thracian handmaidens or
any other uneducated persons, for they have no eye for the situation, but
by every man who has not been brought up a slave.  Such are the two
characters, Theodorus:  the one of the freeman, who has been trained in
liberty and leisure, whom you call the philosopher,--him we cannot blame
because he appears simple and of no account when he has to perform some
menial task, such as packing up bed-clothes, or flavouring a sauce or
fawning speech; the other character is that of the man who is able to do
all this kind of service smartly and neatly, but knows not how to wear his
cloak like a gentleman; still less with the music of discourse can he hymn
the true life aright which is lived by immortals or men blessed of heaven.

THEODORUS:  If you could only persuade everybody, Socrates, as you do me,
of the truth of your words, there would be more peace and fewer evils among
men.

SOCRATES:  Evils, Theodorus, can never pass away; for there must always
remain something which is antagonistic to good.  Having no place among the
gods in heaven, of necessity they hover around the mortal nature, and this
earthly sphere.  Wherefore we ought to fly away from earth to heaven as
quickly as we can; and to fly away is to become like God, as far as this is
possible; and to become like him, is to become holy, just, and wise.  But,
O my friend, you cannot easily convince mankind that they should pursue
virtue or avoid vice, not merely in order that a man may seem to be good,
which is the reason given by the world, and in my judgment is only a
repetition of an old wives' fable.  Whereas, the truth is that God is never
in any way unrighteous--he is perfect righteousness; and he of us who is
the most righteous is most like him.  Herein is seen the true cleverness of
a man, and also his nothingness and want of manhood.  For to know this is
true wisdom and virtue, and ignorance of this is manifest folly and vice. 
All other kinds of wisdom or cleverness, which seem only, such as the
wisdom of politicians, or the wisdom of the arts, are coarse and vulgar. 
The unrighteous man, or the sayer and doer of unholy things, had far better
not be encouraged in the illusion that his roguery is clever; for men glory
in their shame--they fancy that they hear others saying of them, 'These are
not mere good-for-nothing persons, mere burdens of the earth, but such as
men should be who mean to dwell safely in a state.'  Let us tell them that
they are all the more truly what they do not think they are because they do
not know it; for they do not know the penalty of injustice, which above all
things they ought to know--not stripes and death, as they suppose, which
evil-doers often escape, but a penalty which cannot be escaped.

THEODORUS:  What is that?

SOCRATES:  There are two patterns eternally set before them; the one
blessed and divine, the other godless and wretched:  but they do not see
them, or perceive that in their utter folly and infatuation they are
growing like the one and unlike the other, by reason of their evil deeds;
and the penalty is, that they lead a life answering to the pattern which
they are growing like.  And if we tell them, that unless they depart from
their cunning, the place of innocence will not receive them after death;
and that here on earth, they will live ever in the likeness of their own
evil selves, and with evil friends--when they hear this they in their
superior cunning will seem to be listening to the talk of idiots.

THEODORUS:  Very true, Socrates.

SOCRATES:  Too true, my friend, as I well know; there is, however, one
peculiarity in their case:  when they begin to reason in private about
their dislike of philosophy, if they have the courage to hear the argument
out, and do not run away, they grow at last strangely discontented with
themselves; their rhetoric fades away, and they become helpless as
children.  These however are digressions from which we must now desist, or
they will overflow, and drown the original argument; to which, if you
please, we will now return.

THEODORUS:  For my part, Socrates, I would rather have the digressions, for
at my age I find them easier to follow; but if you wish, let us go back to
the argument.

SOCRATES:  Had we not reached the point at which the partisans of the
perpetual flux, who say that things are as they seem to each one, were
confidently maintaining that the ordinances which the state commanded and
thought just, were just to the state which imposed them, while they were in
force; this was especially asserted of justice; but as to the good, no one
had any longer the hardihood to contend of any ordinances which the state
thought and enacted to be good that these, while they were in force, were
really good;--he who said so would be playing with the name 'good,' and
would not touch the real question--it would be a mockery, would it not?

THEODORUS:  Certainly it would.

SOCRATES:  He ought not to speak of the name, but of the thing which is
contemplated under the name.

THEODORUS:  Right.

SOCRATES:  Whatever be the term used, the good or expedient is the aim of
legislation, and as far as she has an opinion, the state imposes all laws
with a view to the greatest expediency; can legislation have any other aim?

THEODORUS:  Certainly not.

SOCRATES:  But is the aim attained always? do not mistakes often happen?

THEODORUS:  Yes, I think that there are mistakes.

SOCRATES:  The possibility of error will be more distinctly recognised, if
we put the question in reference to the whole class under which the good or
expedient falls.  That whole class has to do with the future, and laws are
passed under the idea that they will be useful in after-time; which, in
other words, is the future.

THEODORUS:  Very true.

SOCRATES:  Suppose now, that we ask Protagoras, or one of his disciples, a
question:--O, Protagoras, we will say to him, Man is, as you declare, the
measure of all things--white, heavy, light:  of all such things he is the
judge; for he has the criterion of them in himself, and when he thinks that
things are such as he experiences them to be, he thinks what is and is true
to himself.  Is it not so?

THEODORUS:  Yes.

SOCRATES:  And do you extend your doctrine, Protagoras (as we shall further
say), to the future as well as to the present; and has he the criterion not
only of what in his opinion is but of what will be, and do things always
happen to him as he expected?  For example, take the case of heat:--When an
ordinary man thinks that he is going to have a fever, and that this kind of
heat is coming on, and another person, who is a physician, thinks the
contrary, whose opinion is likely to prove right?  Or are they both right?
--he will have a heat and fever in his own judgment, and not have a fever
in the physician's judgment?

THEODORUS:  How ludicrous!

SOCRATES:  And the vinegrower, if I am not mistaken, is a better judge of
the sweetness or dryness of the vintage which is not yet gathered than the
harp-player?

THEODORUS:  Certainly.

SOCRATES:  And in musical composition the musician will know better than
the training master what the training master himself will hereafter think
harmonious or the reverse?

THEODORUS:  Of course.

SOCRATES:  And the cook will be a better judge than the guest, who is not a
cook, of the pleasure to be derived from the dinner which is in
preparation; for of present or past pleasure we are not as yet arguing; but
can we say that every one will be to himself the best judge of the pleasure
which will seem to be and will be to him in the future?--nay, would not
you, Protagoras, better guess which arguments in a court would convince any
one of us than the ordinary man?

THEODORUS:  Certainly, Socrates, he used to profess in the strongest manner
that he was the superior of all men in this respect.

SOCRATES:  To be sure, friend:  who would have paid a large sum for the
privilege of talking to him, if he had really persuaded his visitors that
neither a prophet nor any other man was better able to judge what will be
and seem to be in the future than every one could for himself?

THEODORUS:  Who indeed?

SOCRATES:  And legislation and expediency are all concerned with the
future; and every one will admit that states, in passing laws, must often
fail of their highest interests?

THEODORUS:  Quite true.

SOCRATES:  Then we may fairly argue against your master, that he must admit
one man to be wiser than another, and that the wiser is a measure:  but I,
who know nothing, am not at all obliged to accept the honour which the
advocate of Protagoras was just now forcing upon me, whether I would or
not, of being a measure of anything.

THEODORUS:  That is the best refutation of him, Socrates; although he is
also caught when he ascribes truth to the opinions of others, who give the
lie direct to his own opinion.

SOCRATES:  There are many ways, Theodorus, in which the doctrine that every
opinion of every man is true may be refuted; but there is more difficulty
in proving that states of feeling, which are present to a man, and out of
which arise sensations and opinions in accordance with them, are also
untrue.  And very likely I have been talking nonsense about them; for they
may be unassailable, and those who say that there is clear evidence of
them, and that they are matters of knowledge, may probably be right; in
which case our friend Theaetetus was not so far from the mark when he
identified perception and knowledge.  And therefore let us draw nearer, as
the advocate of Protagoras desires; and give the truth of the universal
flux a ring:  is the theory sound or not? at any rate, no small war is
raging about it, and there are combination not a few.

THEODORUS:  No small, war, indeed, for in Ionia the sect makes rapid
strides; the disciples of Heracleitus are most energetic upholders of the
doctrine.

SOCRATES:  Then we are the more bound, my dear Theodorus, to examine the
question from the foundation as it is set forth by themselves.

THEODORUS:  Certainly we are.  About these speculations of Heracleitus,
which, as you say, are as old as Homer, or even older still, the Ephesians
themselves, who profess to know them, are downright mad, and you cannot
talk with them on the subject.  For, in accordance with their text-books,
they are always in motion; but as for dwelling upon an argument or a
question, and quietly asking and answering in turn, they can no more do so
than they can fly; or rather, the determination of these fellows not to
have a particle of rest in them is more than the utmost powers of negation
can express.  If you ask any of them a question, he will produce, as from a
quiver, sayings brief and dark, and shoot them at you; and if you inquire
the reason of what he has said, you will be hit by some other new-fangled
word, and will make no way with any of them, nor they with one another;
their great care is, not to allow of any settled principle either in their
arguments or in their minds, conceiving, as I imagine, that any such
principle would be stationary; for they are at war with the stationary, and
do what they can to drive it out everywhere.

SOCRATES:  I suppose, Theodorus, that you have only seen them when they
were fighting, and have never stayed with them in time of peace, for they
are no friends of yours; and their peace doctrines are only communicated by
them at leisure, as I imagine, to those disciples of theirs whom they want
to make like themselves.

THEODORUS:  Disciples! my good sir, they have none; men of their sort are
not one another's disciples, but they grow up at their own sweet will, and
get their inspiration anywhere, each of them saying of his neighbour that
he knows nothing.  From these men, then, as I was going to remark, you will
never get a reason, whether with their will or without their will; we must
take the question out of their hands, and make the analysis ourselves, as
if we were doing geometrical problem.

SOCRATES:  Quite right too; but as touching the aforesaid problem, have we
not heard from the ancients, who concealed their wisdom from the many in
poetical figures, that Oceanus and Tethys, the origin of all things, are
streams, and that nothing is at rest?  And now the moderns, in their
superior wisdom, have declared the same openly, that the cobbler too may
hear and learn of them, and no longer foolishly imagine that some things
are at rest and others in motion--having learned that all is motion, he
will duly honour his teachers.  I had almost forgotten the opposite
doctrine, Theodorus,

'Alone Being remains unmoved, which is the name for the all.'

This is the language of Parmenides, Melissus, and their followers, who
stoutly maintain that all being is one and self-contained, and has no place
in which to move.  What shall we do, friend, with all these people; for,
advancing step by step, we have imperceptibly got between the combatants,
and, unless we can protect our retreat, we shall pay the penalty of our
rashness--like the players in the palaestra who are caught upon the line,
and are dragged different ways by the two parties.  Therefore I think that
we had better begin by considering those whom we first accosted, 'the
river-gods,' and, if we find any truth in them, we will help them to pull
us over, and try to get away from the others.  But if the partisans of 'the
whole' appear to speak more truly, we will fly off from the party which
would move the immovable, to them.  And if I find that neither of them have
anything reasonable to say, we shall be in a ridiculous position, having so
great a conceit of our own poor opinion and rejecting that of ancient and
famous men.  O Theodorus, do you think that there is any use in proceeding
when the danger is so great?

THEODORUS:  Nay, Socrates, not to examine thoroughly what the two parties
have to say would be quite intolerable.

SOCRATES:  Then examine we must, since you, who were so reluctant to begin,
are so eager to proceed.  The nature of motion appears to be the question
with which we begin.  What do they mean when they say that all things are
in motion?  Is there only one kind of motion, or, as I rather incline to
think, two?  I should like to have your opinion upon this point in addition
to my own, that I may err, if I must err, in your company; tell me, then,
when a thing changes from one place to another, or goes round in the same
place, is not that what is called motion?

THEODORUS:  Yes.

SOCRATES:  Here then we have one kind of motion.  But when a thing,
remaining on the same spot, grows old, or becomes black from being white,
or hard from being soft, or undergoes any other change, may not this be
properly called motion of another kind?

THEODORUS:  I think so.

SOCRATES:  Say rather that it must be so.  Of motion then there are these
two kinds, 'change,' and 'motion in place.'

THEODORUS:  You are right.

SOCRATES:  And now, having made this distinction, let us address ourselves
to those who say that all is motion, and ask them whether all things
according to them have the two kinds of motion, and are changed as well as
move in place, or is one thing moved in both ways, and another in one only?

THEODORUS:  Indeed, I do not know what to answer; but I think they would
say that all things are moved in both ways.

SOCRATES:  Yes, comrade; for, if not, they would have to say that the same
things are in motion and at rest, and there would be no more truth in
saying that all things are in motion, than that all things are at rest.

THEODORUS:  To be sure.

SOCRATES:  And if they are to be in motion, and nothing is to be devoid of
motion, all things must always have every sort of motion?

THEODORUS:  Most true.

SOCRATES:  Consider a further point:  did we not understand them to explain
the generation of heat, whiteness, or anything else, in some such manner as
the following:--were they not saying that each of them is moving between
the agent and the patient, together with a perception, and that the patient
ceases to be a perceiving power and becomes a percipient, and the agent a
quale instead of a quality?  I suspect that quality may appear a strange
and uncouth term to you, and that you do not understand the abstract
expression.  Then I will take concrete instances:  I mean to say that the
producing power or agent becomes neither heat nor whiteness but hot and
white, and the like of other things.  For I must repeat what I said before,
that neither the agent nor patient have any absolute existence, but when
they come together and generate sensations and their objects, the one
becomes a thing of a certain quality, and the other a percipient.  You
remember?

THEODORUS:  Of course.

SOCRATES:  We may leave the details of their theory unexamined, but we must
not forget to ask them the only question with which we are concerned:  Are
all things in motion and flux?

THEODORUS:  Yes, they will reply.

SOCRATES:  And they are moved in both those ways which we distinguished,
that is to say, they move in place and are also changed?

THEODORUS:  Of course, if the motion is to be perfect.

SOCRATES:  If they only moved in place and were not changed, we should be
able to say what is the nature of the things which are in motion and flux?

THEODORUS:  Exactly.

SOCRATES:  But now, since not even white continues to flow white, and
whiteness itself is a flux or change which is passing into another colour,
and is never to be caught standing still, can the name of any colour be
rightly used at all?

THEODORUS:  How is that possible, Socrates, either in the case of this or
of any other quality--if while we are using the word the object is escaping
in the flux?

SOCRATES:  And what would you say of perceptions, such as sight and
hearing, or any other kind of perception?  Is there any stopping in the act
of seeing and hearing?

THEODORUS:  Certainly not, if all things are in motion.

SOCRATES:  Then we must not speak of seeing any more than of not-seeing,
nor of any other perception more than of any non-perception, if all things
partake of every kind of motion?

THEODORUS:  Certainly not.

SOCRATES:  Yet perception is knowledge:  so at least Theaetetus and I were
saying.

THEODORUS:  Very true.

SOCRATES:  Then when we were asked what is knowledge, we no more answered
what is knowledge than what is not knowledge?

THEODORUS:  I suppose not.

SOCRATES:  Here, then, is a fine result:  we corrected our first answer in
our eagerness to prove that nothing is at rest.  But if nothing is at rest,
every answer upon whatever subject is equally right:  you may say that a
thing is or is not thus; or, if you prefer, 'becomes' thus; and if we say
'becomes,' we shall not then hamper them with words expressive of rest.

THEODORUS:  Quite true.

SOCRATES:  Yes, Theodorus, except in saying 'thus' and 'not thus.'  But you
ought not to use the word 'thus,' for there is no motion in 'thus' or in
'not thus.'  The maintainers of the doctrine have as yet no words in which
to express themselves, and must get a new language.  I know of no word that
will suit them, except perhaps 'no how,' which is perfectly indefinite.

THEODORUS:  Yes, that is a manner of speaking in which they will be quite
at home.

SOCRATES:  And so, Theodorus, we have got rid of your friend without
assenting to his doctrine, that every man is the measure of all things--a
wise man only is a measure; neither can we allow that knowledge is
perception, certainly not on the hypothesis of a perpetual flux, unless
perchance our friend Theaetetus is able to convince us that it is.

THEODORUS:  Very good, Socrates; and now that the argument about the
doctrine of Protagoras has been completed, I am absolved from answering;
for this was the agreement.

THEAETETUS:  Not, Theodorus, until you and Socrates have discussed the
doctrine of those who say that all things are at rest, as you were
proposing.

THEODORUS:  You, Theaetetus, who are a young rogue, must not instigate your
elders to a breach of faith, but should prepare to answer Socrates in the
remainder of the argument.

THEAETETUS:  Yes, if he wishes; but I would rather have heard about the
doctrine of rest.

THEODORUS:  Invite Socrates to an argument--invite horsemen to the open
plain; do but ask him, and he will answer.

SOCRATES:  Nevertheless, Theodorus, I am afraid that I shall not be able to
comply with the request of Theaetetus.

THEODORUS:  Not comply! for what reason?

SOCRATES:  My reason is that I have a kind of reverence; not so much for
Melissus and the others, who say that 'All is one and at rest,' as for the
great leader himself, Parmenides, venerable and awful, as in Homeric
language he may be called;--him I should be ashamed to approach in a spirit
unworthy of him.  I met him when he was an old man, and I was a mere youth,
and he appeared to me to have a glorious depth of mind.  And I am afraid
that we may not understand his words, and may be still further from
understanding his meaning; above all I fear that the nature of knowledge,
which is the main subject of our discussion, may be thrust out of sight by
the unbidden guests who will come pouring in upon our feast of discourse,
if we let them in--besides, the question which is now stirring is of
immense extent, and will be treated unfairly if only considered by the way;
or if treated adequately and at length, will put into the shade the other
question of knowledge.  Neither the one nor the other can be allowed; but I
must try by my art of midwifery to deliver Theaetetus of his conceptions
about knowledge.

THEAETETUS:  Very well; do so if you will.

SOCRATES:  Then now, Theaetetus, take another view of the subject:  you
answered that knowledge is perception?

THEAETETUS:  I did.

SOCRATES:  And if any one were to ask you:  With what does a man see black
and white colours? and with what does he hear high and low sounds?--you
would say, if I am not mistaken, 'With the eyes and with the ears.'

THEAETETUS:  I should.

SOCRATES:  The free use of words and phrases, rather than minute precision,
is generally characteristic of a liberal education, and the opposite is
pedantic; but sometimes precision is necessary, and I believe that the
answer which you have just given is open to the charge of incorrectness;
for which is more correct, to say that we see or hear with the eyes and
with the ears, or through the eyes and through the ears.

THEAETETUS:  I should say 'through,' Socrates, rather than 'with.'

SOCRATES:  Yes, my boy, for no one can suppose that in each of us, as in a
sort of Trojan horse, there are perched a number of unconnected senses,
which do not all meet in some one nature, the mind, or whatever we please
to call it, of which they are the instruments, and with which through them
we perceive objects of sense.

THEAETETUS:  I agree with you in that opinion.

SOCRATES:  The reason why I am thus precise is, because I want to know
whether, when we perceive black and white through the eyes, and again,
other qualities through other organs, we do not perceive them with one and
the same part of ourselves, and, if you were asked, you might refer all
such perceptions to the body.  Perhaps, however, I had better allow you to
answer for yourself and not interfere.  Tell me, then, are not the organs
through which you perceive warm and hard and light and sweet, organs of the
body?

THEAETETUS:  Of the body, certainly.

SOCRATES:  And you would admit that what you perceive through one faculty
you cannot perceive through another; the objects of hearing, for example,
cannot be perceived through sight, or the objects of sight through hearing?

THEAETETUS:  Of course not.

SOCRATES:  If you have any thought about both of them, this common
perception cannot come to you, either through the one or the other organ?

THEAETETUS:  It cannot.

SOCRATES:  How about sounds and colours:  in the first place you would
admit that they both exist?

THEAETETUS:  Yes.

SOCRATES:  And that either of them is different from the other, and the
same with itself?

THEAETETUS:  Certainly.

SOCRATES:  And that both are two and each of them one?

THEAETETUS:  Yes.

SOCRATES:  You can further observe whether they are like or unlike one
another?

THEAETETUS:  I dare say.

SOCRATES:  But through what do you perceive all this about them? for
neither through hearing nor yet through seeing can you apprehend that which
they have in common.  Let me give you an illustration of the point at
issue:--If there were any meaning in asking whether sounds and colours are
saline or not, you would be able to tell me what faculty would consider the
question.  It would not be sight or hearing, but some other.

THEAETETUS:  Certainly; the faculty of taste.

SOCRATES:  Very good; and now tell me what is the power which discerns, not
only in sensible objects, but in all things, universal notions, such as
those which are called being and not-being, and those others about which we
were just asking--what organs will you assign for the perception of these
notions?

THEAETETUS:  You are thinking of being and not being, likeness and
unlikeness, sameness and difference, and also of unity and other numbers
which are applied to objects of sense; and you mean to ask, through what
bodily organ the soul perceives odd and even numbers and other arithmetical
conceptions.

SOCRATES:  You follow me excellently, Theaetetus; that is precisely what I
am asking.

THEAETETUS:  Indeed, Socrates, I cannot answer; my only notion is, that
these, unlike objects of sense, have no separate organ, but that the mind,
by a power of her own, contemplates the universals in all things.

SOCRATES:  You are a beauty, Theaetetus, and not ugly, as Theodorus was
saying; for he who utters the beautiful is himself beautiful and good.  And
besides being beautiful, you have done me a kindness in releasing me from a
very long discussion, if you are clear that the soul views some things by
herself and others through the bodily organs.  For that was my own opinion,
and I wanted you to agree with me.

THEAETETUS:  I am quite clear.

SOCRATES:  And to which class would you refer being or essence; for this,
of all our notions, is the most universal?

THEAETETUS:  I should say, to that class which the soul aspires to know of
herself.

SOCRATES:  And would you say this also of like and unlike, same and other?

THEAETETUS:  Yes.

SOCRATES:  And would you say the same of the noble and base, and of good
and evil?

THEAETETUS:  These I conceive to be notions which are essentially relative,
and which the soul also perceives by comparing in herself things past and
present with the future.

SOCRATES:  And does she not perceive the hardness of that which is hard by
the touch, and the softness of that which is soft equally by the touch?

THEAETETUS:  Yes.

SOCRATES:  But their essence and what they are, and their opposition to one
another, and the essential nature of this opposition, the soul herself
endeavours to decide for us by the review and comparison of them?

THEAETETUS:  Certainly.

SOCRATES:  The simple sensations which reach the soul through the body are
given at birth to men and animals by nature, but their reflections on the
being and use of them are slowly and hardly gained, if they are ever
gained, by education and long experience.

THEAETETUS:  Assuredly.

SOCRATES:  And can a man attain truth who fails of attaining being?

THEAETETUS:  Impossible.

SOCRATES:  And can he who misses the truth of anything, have a knowledge of
that thing?

THEAETETUS:  He cannot.

SOCRATES:  Then knowledge does not consist in impressions of sense, but in
reasoning about them; in that only, and not in the mere impression, truth
and being can be attained?

THEAETETUS:  Clearly.

SOCRATES:  And would you call the two processes by the same name, when
there is so great a difference between them?

THEAETETUS:  That would certainly not be right.

SOCRATES:  And what name would you give to seeing, hearing, smelling, being
cold and being hot?

THEAETETUS:  I should call all of them perceiving--what other name could be
given to them?

SOCRATES:  Perception would be the collective name of them?

THEAETETUS:  Certainly.

SOCRATES:  Which, as we say, has no part in the attainment of truth any
more than of being?

THEAETETUS:  Certainly not.

SOCRATES:  And therefore not in science or knowledge?

THEAETETUS:  No.

SOCRATES:  Then perception, Theaetetus, can never be the same as knowledge
or science?

THEAETETUS:  Clearly not, Socrates; and knowledge has now been most
distinctly proved to be different from perception.

SOCRATES:  But the original aim of our discussion was to find out rather
what knowledge is than what it is not; at the same time we have made some
progress, for we no longer seek for knowledge in perception at all, but in
that other process, however called, in which the mind is alone and engaged
with being.

THEAETETUS:  You mean, Socrates, if I am not mistaken, what is called
thinking or opining.

SOCRATES:  You conceive truly.  And now, my friend, please to begin again
at this point; and having wiped out of your memory all that has preceded,
see if you have arrived at any clearer view, and once more say what is
knowledge.

THEAETETUS:  I cannot say, Socrates, that all opinion is knowledge, because
there may be a false opinion; but I will venture to assert, that knowledge
is true opinion:  let this then be my reply; and if this is hereafter
disproved, I must try to find another.

SOCRATES:  That is the way in which you ought to answer, Theaetetus, and
not in your former hesitating strain, for if we are bold we shall gain one
of two advantages; either we shall find what we seek, or we shall be less
likely to think that we know what we do not know--in either case we shall
be richly rewarded.  And now, what are you saying?--Are there two sorts of
opinion, one true and the other false; and do you define knowledge to be
the true?

THEAETETUS:  Yes, according to my present view.

SOCRATES:  Is it still worth our while to resume the discussion touching
opinion?

THEAETETUS:  To what are you alluding?

SOCRATES:  There is a point which often troubles me, and is a great
perplexity to me, both in regard to myself and others.  I cannot make out
the nature or origin of the mental experience to which I refer.

THEAETETUS:  Pray what is it?

SOCRATES:  How there can be false opinion--that difficulty still troubles
the eye of my mind; and I am uncertain whether I shall leave the question,
or begin over again in a new way.

THEAETETUS:  Begin again, Socrates,--at least if you think that there is
the slightest necessity for doing so.  Were not you and Theodorus just now
remarking very truly, that in discussions of this kind we may take our own
time?

SOCRATES:  You are quite right, and perhaps there will be no harm in
retracing our steps and beginning again.  Better a little which is well
done, than a great deal imperfectly.

THEAETETUS:  Certainly.

SOCRATES:  Well, and what is the difficulty?  Do we not speak of false
opinion, and say that one man holds a false and another a true opinion, as
though there were some natural distinction between them?

THEAETETUS:  We certainly say so.

SOCRATES:  All things and everything are either known or not known.  I
leave out of view the intermediate conceptions of learning and forgetting,
because they have nothing to do with our present question.

THEAETETUS:  There can be no doubt, Socrates, if you exclude these, that
there is no other alternative but knowing or not knowing a thing.

SOCRATES:  That point being now determined, must we not say that he who has
an opinion, must have an opinion about something which he knows or does not
know?

THEAETETUS:  He must.

SOCRATES:  He who knows, cannot but know; and he who does not know, cannot
know?

THEAETETUS:  Of course.

SOCRATES:  What shall we say then?  When a man has a false opinion does he
think that which he knows to be some other thing which he knows, and
knowing both, is he at the same time ignorant of both?

THEAETETUS:  That, Socrates, is impossible.

SOCRATES:  But perhaps he thinks of something which he does not know as
some other thing which he does not know; for example, he knows neither
Theaetetus nor Socrates, and yet he fancies that Theaetetus is Socrates, or
Socrates Theaetetus?

THEAETETUS:  How can he?

SOCRATES:  But surely he cannot suppose what he knows to be what he does
not know, or what he does not know to be what he knows?

THEAETETUS:  That would be monstrous.

SOCRATES:  Where, then, is false opinion?  For if all things are either
known or unknown, there can be no opinion which is not comprehended under
this alternative, and so false opinion is excluded.

THEAETETUS:  Most true.

SOCRATES:  Suppose that we remove the question out of the sphere of knowing
or not knowing, into that of being and not-being.

THEAETETUS:  What do you mean?

SOCRATES:  May we not suspect the simple truth to be that he who thinks
about anything, that which is not, will necessarily think what is false,
whatever in other respects may be the state of his mind?

THEAETETUS:  That, again, is not unlikely, Socrates.

SOCRATES:  Then suppose some one to say to us, Theaetetus:--Is it possible
for any man to think that which is not, either as a self-existent substance
or as a predicate of something else?  And suppose that we answer, 'Yes, he
can, when he thinks what is not true.'--That will be our answer?

THEAETETUS:  Yes.

SOCRATES:  But is there any parallel to this?

THEAETETUS:  What do you mean?

SOCRATES:  Can a man see something and yet see nothing?

THEAETETUS:  Impossible.

SOCRATES:  But if he sees any one thing, he sees something that exists.  Do
you suppose that what is one is ever to be found among non-existing things?

THEAETETUS:  I do not.

SOCRATES:  He then who sees some one thing, sees something which is?

THEAETETUS:  Clearly.

SOCRATES:  And he who hears anything, hears some one thing, and hears
that which is?

THEAETETUS:  Yes.

SOCRATES:  And he who touches anything, touches something which is one and
therefore is?

THEAETETUS:  That again is true.

SOCRATES:  And does not he who thinks, think some one thing?

THEAETETUS:  Certainly.

SOCRATES:  And does not he who thinks some one thing, think something which
is?

THEAETETUS:  I agree.

SOCRATES:  Then he who thinks of that which is not, thinks of nothing?

THEAETETUS:  Clearly.

SOCRATES:  And he who thinks of nothing, does not think at all?

THEAETETUS:  Obviously.

SOCRATES:  Then no one can think that which is not, either as a self-
existent substance or as a predicate of something else?

THEAETETUS:  Clearly not.

SOCRATES:  Then to think falsely is different from thinking that which is
not?

THEAETETUS:  It would seem so.

SOCRATES:  Then false opinion has no existence in us, either in the sphere
of being or of knowledge?

THEAETETUS:  Certainly not.

SOCRATES:  But may not the following be the description of what we express
by this name?

THEAETETUS:  What?

SOCRATES:  May we not suppose that false opinion or thought is a sort of
heterodoxy; a person may make an exchange in his mind, and say that one
real object is another real object.  For thus he always thinks that which
is, but he puts one thing in place of another; and missing the aim of his
thoughts, he may be truly said to have false opinion.

THEAETETUS:  Now you appear to me to have spoken the exact truth:  when a
man puts the base in the place of the noble, or the noble in the place of
the base, then he has truly false opinion.

SOCRATES:  I see, Theaetetus, that your fear has disappeared, and that you
are beginning to despise me.

THEAETETUS:  What makes you say so?

SOCRATES:  You think, if I am not mistaken, that your 'truly false' is safe
from censure, and that I shall never ask whether there can be a swift which
is slow, or a heavy which is light, or any other self-contradictory thing,
which works, not according to its own nature, but according to that of its
opposite.  But I will not insist upon this, for I do not wish needlessly to
discourage you.  And so you are satisfied that false opinion is heterodoxy,
or the thought of something else?

THEAETETUS:  I am.

SOCRATES:  It is possible then upon your view for the mind to conceive of
one thing as another?

THEAETETUS:  True.

SOCRATES:  But must not the mind, or thinking power, which misplaces them,
have a conception either of both objects or of one of them?

THEAETETUS:  Certainly.

SOCRATES:  Either together or in succession?

THEAETETUS:  Very good.

SOCRATES:  And do you mean by conceiving, the same which I mean?

THEAETETUS:  What is that?

SOCRATES:  I mean the conversation which the soul holds with herself in
considering of anything.  I speak of what I scarcely understand; but the
soul when thinking appears to me to be just talking--asking questions of
herself and answering them, affirming and denying.  And when she has
arrived at a decision, either gradually or by a sudden impulse, and has at
last agreed, and does not doubt, this is called her opinion.  I say, then,
that to form an opinion is to speak, and opinion is a word spoken,--I mean,
to oneself and in silence, not aloud or to another:  What think you?

THEAETETUS:  I agree.

SOCRATES:  Then when any one thinks of one thing as another, he is saying
to himself that one thing is another?

THEAETETUS:  Yes.

SOCRATES:  But do you ever remember saying to yourself that the noble is
certainly base, or the unjust just; or, best of all--have you ever
attempted to convince yourself that one thing is another?  Nay, not even in
sleep, did you ever venture to say to yourself that odd is even, or
anything of the kind?

THEAETETUS:  Never.

SOCRATES:  And do you suppose that any other man, either in his senses or
out of them, ever seriously tried to persuade himself that an ox is a
horse, or that two are one?

THEAETETUS:  Certainly not.

SOCRATES:  But if thinking is talking to oneself, no one speaking and
thinking of two objects, and apprehending them both in his soul, will say
and think that the one is the other of them, and I must add, that even you,
lover of dispute as you are, had better let the word 'other' alone (i.e.
not insist that 'one' and 'other' are the same (Both words in Greek are
called eteron: compare Parmen.; Euthyd.)).  I mean to say, that no one
thinks the noble to be base, or anything of the kind.

THEAETETUS:  I will give up the word 'other,' Socrates; and I agree to what
you say.

SOCRATES:  If a man has both of them in his thoughts, he cannot think that
the one of them is the other?

THEAETETUS:  True.

SOCRATES:  Neither, if he has one of them only in his mind and not the
other, can he think that one is the other?

THEAETETUS:  True; for we should have to suppose that he apprehends that
which is not in his thoughts at all.

SOCRATES:  Then no one who has either both or only one of the two objects
in his mind can think that the one is the other.  And therefore, he who
maintains that false opinion is heterodoxy is talking nonsense; for neither
in this, any more than in the previous way, can false opinion exist in us.

THEAETETUS:  No.

SOCRATES:  But if, Theaetetus, this is not admitted, we shall be driven
into many absurdities.

THEAETETUS:  What are they?

SOCRATES:  I will not tell you until I have endeavoured to consider the
matter from every point of view.  For I should be ashamed of us if we were
driven in our perplexity to admit the absurd consequences of which I speak. 
But if we find the solution, and get away from them, we may regard them
only as the difficulties of others, and the ridicule will not attach to us. 
On the other hand, if we utterly fail, I suppose that we must be humble,
and allow the argument to trample us under foot, as the sea-sick passenger
is trampled upon by the sailor, and to do anything to us.  Listen, then,
while I tell you how I hope to find a way out of our difficulty.

THEAETETUS:  Let me hear.

SOCRATES:  I think that we were wrong in denying that a man could think
what he knew to be what he did not know; and that there is a way in which
such a deception is possible.

THEAETETUS:  You mean to say, as I suspected at the time, that I may know
Socrates, and at a distance see some one who is unknown to me, and whom I
mistake for him--then the deception will occur?

SOCRATES:  But has not that position been relinquished by us, because
involving the absurdity that we should know and not know the things which
we know?

THEAETETUS:  True.

SOCRATES:  Let us make the assertion in another form, which may or may not
have a favourable issue; but as we are in a great strait, every argument
should be turned over and tested.  Tell me, then, whether I am right in
saying that you may learn a thing which at one time you did not know?

THEAETETUS:  Certainly you may.

SOCRATES:  And another and another?

THEAETETUS:  Yes.

SOCRATES:  I would have you imagine, then, that there exists in the mind of
man a block of wax, which is of different sizes in different men; harder,
moister, and having more or less of purity in one than another, and in some
of an intermediate quality.

THEAETETUS:  I see.

SOCRATES:  Let us say that this tablet is a gift of Memory, the mother of
the Muses; and that when we wish to remember anything which we have seen,
or heard, or thought in our own minds, we hold the wax to the perceptions
and thoughts, and in that material receive the impression of them as from
the seal of a ring; and that we remember and know what is imprinted as long
as the image lasts; but when the image is effaced, or cannot be taken, then
we forget and do not know.

THEAETETUS:  Very good.

SOCRATES:  Now, when a person has this knowledge, and is considering
something which he sees or hears, may not false opinion arise in the
following manner?

THEAETETUS:  In what manner?

SOCRATES:  When he thinks what he knows, sometimes to be what he knows, and
sometimes to be what he does not know.  We were wrong before in denying the
possibility of this.

THEAETETUS:  And how would you amend the former statement?

SOCRATES:  I should begin by making a list of the impossible cases which
must be excluded.  (1) No one can think one thing to be another when he
does not perceive either of them, but has the memorial or seal of both of
them in his mind; nor can any mistaking of one thing for another occur,
when he only knows one, and does not know, and has no impression of the
other; nor can he think that one thing which he does not know is another
thing which he does not know, or that what he does not know is what he
knows; nor (2) that one thing which he perceives is another thing which he
perceives, or that something which he perceives is something which he does
not perceive; or that something which he does not perceive is something
else which he does not perceive; or that something which he does not
perceive is something which he perceives; nor again (3) can he think that
something which he knows and perceives, and of which he has the impression
coinciding with sense, is something else which he knows and perceives, and
of which he has the impression coinciding with sense;--this last case, if
possible, is still more inconceivable than the others; nor (4) can he think
that something which he knows and perceives, and of which he has the
memorial coinciding with sense, is something else which he knows; nor so
long as these agree, can he think that a thing which he knows and perceives
is another thing which he perceives; or that a thing which he does not know
and does not perceive, is the same as another thing which he does not know
and does not perceive;--nor again, can he suppose that a thing which he
does not know and does not perceive is the same as another thing which he
does not know; or that a thing which he does not know and does not perceive
is another thing which he does not perceive:--All these utterly and
absolutely exclude the possibility of false opinion.  The only cases, if
any, which remain, are the following.

THEAETETUS:  What are they?  If you tell me, I may perhaps understand you
better; but at present I am unable to follow you.

SOCRATES:  A person may think that some things which he knows, or which he
perceives and does not know, are some other things which he knows and
perceives; or that some things which he knows and perceives, are other
things which he knows and perceives.

THEAETETUS:  I understand you less than ever now.

SOCRATES:  Hear me once more, then:--I, knowing Theodorus, and remembering
in my own mind what sort of person he is, and also what sort of person
Theaetetus is, at one time see them, and at another time do not see them,
and sometimes I touch them, and at another time not, or at one time I may
hear them or perceive them in some other way, and at another time not
perceive them, but still I remember them, and know them in my own mind.

THEAETETUS:  Very true.

SOCRATES:  Then, first of all, I want you to understand that a man may or
may not perceive sensibly that which he knows.

THEAETETUS:  True.

SOCRATES:  And that which he does not know will sometimes not be perceived
by him and sometimes will be perceived and only perceived?

THEAETETUS:  That is also true.

SOCRATES:  See whether you can follow me better now:  Socrates can
recognize Theodorus and Theaetetus, but he sees neither of them, nor does
he perceive them in any other way; he cannot then by any possibility
imagine in his own mind that Theaetetus is Theodorus.  Am I not right?

THEAETETUS:  You are quite right.

SOCRATES:  Then that was the first case of which I spoke.

THEAETETUS:  Yes.

SOCRATES:  The second case was, that I, knowing one of you and not knowing
the other, and perceiving neither, can never think him whom I know to be
him whom I do not know.

THEAETETUS:  True.

SOCRATES:  In the third case, not knowing and not perceiving either of you,
I cannot think that one of you whom I do not know is the other whom I do
not know.  I need not again go over the catalogue of excluded cases, in
which I cannot form a false opinion about you and Theodorus, either when I
know both or when I am in ignorance of both, or when I know one and not the
other.  And the same of perceiving:  do you understand me?

THEAETETUS:  I do.

SOCRATES:  The only possibility of erroneous opinion is, when knowing you
and Theodorus, and having on the waxen block the impression of both of you
given as by a seal, but seeing you imperfectly and at a distance, I try to
assign the right impression of memory to the right visual impression, and
to fit this into its own print:  if I succeed, recognition will take place;
but if I fail and transpose them, putting the foot into the wrong shoe--
that is to say, putting the vision of either of you on to the wrong
impression, or if my mind, like the sight in a mirror, which is transferred
from right to left, err by reason of some similar affection, then
'heterodoxy' and false opinion ensues.

THEAETETUS:  Yes, Socrates, you have described the nature of opinion with
wonderful exactness.

SOCRATES:  Or again, when I know both of you, and perceive as well as know
one of you, but not the other, and my knowledge of him does not accord with
perception--that was the case put by me just now which you did not
understand.

THEAETETUS:  No, I did not.

SOCRATES:  I meant to say, that when a person knows and perceives one of
you, his knowledge coincides with his perception, he will never think him
to be some other person, whom he knows and perceives, and the knowledge of
whom coincides with his perception--for that also was a case supposed.

THEAETETUS:  True.

SOCRATES:  But there was an omission of the further case, in which, as we
now say, false opinion may arise, when knowing both, and seeing, or having
some other sensible perception of both, I fail in holding the seal over
against the corresponding sensation; like a bad archer, I miss and fall
wide of the mark--and this is called falsehood.

THEAETETUS:  Yes; it is rightly so called.

SOCRATES:  When, therefore, perception is present to one of the seals or
impressions but not to the other, and the mind fits the seal of the absent
perception on the one which is present, in any case of this sort the mind
is deceived; in a word, if our view is sound, there can be no error or
deception about things which a man does not know and has never perceived,
but only in things which are known and perceived; in these alone opinion
turns and twists about, and becomes alternately true and false;--true when
the seals and impressions of sense meet straight and opposite--false when
they go awry and crooked.

THEAETETUS:  And is not that, Socrates, nobly said?

SOCRATES:  Nobly! yes; but wait a little and hear the explanation, and then
you will say so with more reason; for to think truly is noble and to be
deceived is base.

THEAETETUS:  Undoubtedly.

SOCRATES:  And the origin of truth and error is as follows:--When the wax
in the soul of any one is deep and abundant, and smooth and perfectly
tempered, then the impressions which pass through the senses and sink into
the heart of the soul, as Homer says in a parable, meaning to indicate the
likeness of the soul to wax (Kerh Kerhos); these, I say, being pure and
clear, and having a sufficient depth of wax, are also lasting, and minds,
such as these, easily learn and easily retain, and are not liable to
confusion, but have true thoughts, for they have plenty of room, and having
clear impressions of things, as we term them, quickly distribute them into
their proper places on the block.  And such men are called wise.  Do you
agree?

THEAETETUS:  Entirely.

SOCRATES:  But when the heart of any one is shaggy--a quality which the
all-wise poet commends, or muddy and of impure wax, or very soft, or very
hard, then there is a corresponding defect in the mind--the soft are good
at learning, but apt to forget; and the hard are the reverse; the shaggy
and rugged and gritty, or those who have an admixture of earth or dung in
their composition, have the impressions indistinct, as also the hard, for
there is no depth in them; and the soft too are indistinct, for their
impressions are easily confused and effaced.  Yet greater is the
indistinctness when they are all jostled together in a little soul, which
has no room.  These are the natures which have false opinion; for when they
see or hear or think of anything, they are slow in assigning the right
objects to the right impressions--in their stupidity they confuse them, and
are apt to see and hear and think amiss--and such men are said to be
deceived in their knowledge of objects, and ignorant.

THEAETETUS:  No man, Socrates, can say anything truer than that.

SOCRATES:  Then now we may admit the existence of false opinion in us?

THEAETETUS:  Certainly.

SOCRATES:  And of true opinion also?

THEAETETUS:  Yes.

SOCRATES:  We have at length satisfactorily proven beyond a doubt there are
these two sorts of opinion?

THEAETETUS:  Undoubtedly.

SOCRATES:  Alas, Theaetetus, what a tiresome creature is a man who is fond
of talking!

THEAETETUS:  What makes you say so?

SOCRATES:  Because I am disheartened at my own stupidity and tiresome
garrulity; for what other term will describe the habit of a man who is
always arguing on all sides of a question; whose dulness cannot be
convinced, and who will never leave off?

THEAETETUS:  But what puts you out of heart?

SOCRATES:  I am not only out of heart, but in positive despair; for I do
not know what to answer if any one were to ask me:--O Socrates, have you
indeed discovered that false opinion arises neither in the comparison of
perceptions with one another nor yet in thought, but in union of thought
and perception?  Yes, I shall say, with the complacence of one who thinks
that he has made a noble discovery.

THEAETETUS:  I see no reason why we should be ashamed of our demonstration,
Socrates.

SOCRATES:  He will say:  You mean to argue that the man whom we only think
of and do not see, cannot be confused with the horse which we do not see or
touch, but only think of and do not perceive?  That I believe to be my
meaning, I shall reply.

THEAETETUS:  Quite right.

SOCRATES:  Well, then, he will say, according to that argument, the number
eleven, which is only thought, can never be mistaken for twelve, which is
only thought:  How would you answer him?

THEAETETUS:  I should say that a mistake may very likely arise between the
eleven or twelve which are seen or handled, but that no similar mistake can
arise between the eleven and twelve which are in the mind.

SOCRATES:  Well, but do you think that no one ever put before his own mind
five and seven,--I do not mean five or seven men or horses, but five or
seven in the abstract, which, as we say, are recorded on the waxen block,
and in which false opinion is held to be impossible; did no man ever ask
himself how many these numbers make when added together, and answer that
they are eleven, while another thinks that they are twelve, or would all
agree in thinking and saying that they are twelve?

THEAETETUS:  Certainly not; many would think that they are eleven, and in
the higher numbers the chance of error is greater still; for I assume you
to be speaking of numbers in general.

SOCRATES:  Exactly; and I want you to consider whether this does not imply
that the twelve in the waxen block are supposed to be eleven?

THEAETETUS:  Yes, that seems to be the case.

SOCRATES:  Then do we not come back to the old difficulty?  For he who
makes such a mistake does think one thing which he knows to be another
thing which he knows; but this, as we said, was impossible, and afforded an
irresistible proof of the non-existence of false opinion, because otherwise
the same person would inevitably know and not know the same thing at the
same time.

THEAETETUS:  Most true.

SOCRATES:  Then false opinion cannot be explained as a confusion of thought
and sense, for in that case we could not have been mistaken about pure
conceptions of thought; and thus we are obliged to say, either that false
opinion does not exist, or that a man may not know that which he knows;--
which alternative do you prefer?

THEAETETUS:  It is hard to determine, Socrates.

SOCRATES:  And yet the argument will scarcely admit of both.  But, as we
are at our wits' end, suppose that we do a shameless thing?

THEAETETUS:  What is it?

SOCRATES:  Let us attempt to explain the verb 'to know.'

THEAETETUS:  And why should that be shameless?

SOCRATES:  You seem not to be aware that the whole of our discussion from
the very beginning has been a search after knowledge, of which we are
assumed not to know the nature.

THEAETETUS:  Nay, but I am well aware.

SOCRATES:  And is it not shameless when we do not know what knowledge is,
to be explaining the verb 'to know'?  The truth is, Theaetetus, that we
have long been infected with logical impurity.  Thousands of times have we
repeated the words 'we know,' and 'do not know,' and 'we have or have not
science or knowledge,' as if we could understand what we are saying to one
another, so long as we remain ignorant about knowledge; and at this moment
we are using the words 'we understand,' 'we are ignorant,' as though we
could still employ them when deprived of knowledge or science.

THEAETETUS:  But if you avoid these expressions, Socrates, how will you
ever argue at all?

SOCRATES:  I could not, being the man I am.  The case would be different if
I were a true hero of dialectic:  and O that such an one were present! for
he would have told us to avoid the use of these terms; at the same time he
would not have spared in you and me the faults which I have noted.  But,
seeing that we are no great wits, shall I venture to say what knowing is?
for I think that the attempt may be worth making.

THEAETETUS:  Then by all means venture, and no one shall find fault with
you for using the forbidden terms.

SOCRATES:  You have heard the common explanation of the verb 'to know'?

THEAETETUS:  I think so, but I do not remember it at the moment.

SOCRATES:  They explain the word 'to know' as meaning 'to have knowledge.'

THEAETETUS:  True.

SOCRATES:  I should like to make a slight change, and say 'to possess'
knowledge.

THEAETETUS:  How do the two expressions differ?

SOCRATES:  Perhaps there may be no difference; but still I should like you
to hear my view, that you may help me to test it.

THEAETETUS:  I will, if I can.

SOCRATES:  I should distinguish 'having' from 'possessing':  for example, a
man may buy and keep under his control a garment which he does not wear;
and then we should say, not that he has, but that he possesses the garment.

THEAETETUS:  It would be the correct expression.

SOCRATES:  Well, may not a man 'possess' and yet not 'have' knowledge in
the sense of which I am speaking?  As you may suppose a man to have caught
wild birds--doves or any other birds--and to be keeping them in an aviary
which he has constructed at home; we might say of him in one sense, that he
always has them because he possesses them, might we not?

THEAETETUS:  Yes.

SOCRATES:  And yet, in another sense, he has none of them; but they are in
his power, and he has got them under his hand in an enclosure of his own,
and can take and have them whenever he likes;--he can catch any which he
likes, and let the bird go again, and he may do so as often as he pleases.

THEAETETUS:  True.

SOCRATES:  Once more, then, as in what preceded we made a sort of waxen
figment in the mind, so let us now suppose that in the mind of each man
there is an aviary of all sorts of birds--some flocking together apart from
the rest, others in small groups, others solitary, flying anywhere and
everywhere.

THEAETETUS:  Let us imagine such an aviary--and what is to follow?

SOCRATES:  We may suppose that the birds are kinds of knowledge, and that
when we were children, this receptacle was empty; whenever a man has gotten
and detained in the enclosure a kind of knowledge, he may be said to have
learned or discovered the thing which is the subject of the knowledge:  and
this is to know.

THEAETETUS:  Granted.

SOCRATES:  And further, when any one wishes to catch any of these
knowledges or sciences, and having taken, to hold it, and again to let them
go, how will he express himself?--will he describe the 'catching' of them
and the original 'possession' in the same words?  I will make my meaning
clearer by an example:--You admit that there is an art of arithmetic?

THEAETETUS:  To be sure.

SOCRATES:  Conceive this under the form of a hunt after the science of odd
and even in general.

THEAETETUS:  I follow.

SOCRATES:  Having the use of the art, the arithmetician, if I am not
mistaken, has the conceptions of number under his hand, and can transmit
them to another.

THEAETETUS:  Yes.

SOCRATES:  And when transmitting them he may be said to teach them, and
when receiving to learn them, and when receiving to learn them, and when
having them in possession in the aforesaid aviary he may be said to know
them.

THEAETETUS:  Exactly.

SOCRATES:  Attend to what follows:  must not the perfect arithmetician know
all numbers, for he has the science of all numbers in his mind?

THEAETETUS:  True.

SOCRATES:  And he can reckon abstract numbers in his head, or things about
him which are numerable?

THEAETETUS:  Of course he can.

SOCRATES:  And to reckon is simply to consider how much such and such a
number amounts to?

THEAETETUS:  Very true.

SOCRATES:  And so he appears to be searching into something which he knows,
as if he did not know it, for we have already admitted that he knows all
numbers;--you have heard these perplexing questions raised?

THEAETETUS:  I have.

SOCRATES:  May we not pursue the image of the doves, and say that the chase
after knowledge is of two kinds? one kind is prior to possession and for
the sake of possession, and the other for the sake of taking and holding in
the hands that which is possessed already.  And thus, when a man has
learned and known something long ago, he may resume and get hold of the
knowledge which he has long possessed, but has not at hand in his mind.

THEAETETUS:  True.

SOCRATES:  That was my reason for asking how we ought to speak when an
arithmetician sets about numbering, or a grammarian about reading?  Shall
we say, that although he knows, he comes back to himself to learn what he
already knows?

THEAETETUS:  It would be too absurd, Socrates.

SOCRATES:  Shall we say then that he is going to read or number what he
does not know, although we have admitted that he knows all letters and all
numbers?

THEAETETUS:  That, again, would be an absurdity.

SOCRATES:  Then shall we say that about names we care nothing?--any one may
twist and turn the words 'knowing' and 'learning' in any way which he
likes, but since we have determined that the possession of knowledge is not
the having or using it, we do assert that a man cannot not possess that
which he possesses; and, therefore, in no case can a man not know that
which he knows, but he may get a false opinion about it; for he may have
the knowledge, not of this particular thing, but of some other;--when the
various numbers and forms of knowledge are flying about in the aviary, and
wishing to capture a certain sort of knowledge out of the general store, he
takes the wrong one by mistake, that is to say, when he thought eleven to
be twelve, he got hold of the ring-dove which he had in his mind, when he
wanted the pigeon.

THEAETETUS:  A very rational explanation.

SOCRATES:  But when he catches the one which he wants, then he is not
deceived, and has an opinion of what is, and thus false and true opinion
may exist, and the difficulties which were previously raised disappear.  I
dare say that you agree with me, do you not?

THEAETETUS:  Yes.

SOCRATES:  And so we are rid of the difficulty of a man's not knowing what
he knows, for we are not driven to the inference that he does not possess
what he possesses, whether he be or be not deceived.  And yet I fear that a
greater difficulty is looking in at the window.

THEAETETUS:  What is it?

SOCRATES:  How can the exchange of one knowledge for another ever become
false opinion?

THEAETETUS:  What do you mean?

SOCRATES:  In the first place, how can a man who has the knowledge of
anything be ignorant of that which he knows, not by reason of ignorance,
but by reason of his own knowledge?  And, again, is it not an extreme
absurdity that he should suppose another thing to be this, and this to be
another thing;--that, having knowledge present with him in his mind, he
should still know nothing and be ignorant of all things?--you might as well
argue that ignorance may make a man know, and blindness make him see, as
that knowledge can make him ignorant.

THEAETETUS:  Perhaps, Socrates, we may have been wrong in making only forms
of knowledge our birds:  whereas there ought to have been forms of
ignorance as well, flying about together in the mind, and then he who
sought to take one of them might sometimes catch a form of knowledge, and
sometimes a form of ignorance; and thus he would have a false opinion from
ignorance, but a true one from knowledge, about the same thing.

SOCRATES:  I cannot help praising you, Theaetetus, and yet I must beg you
to reconsider your words.  Let us grant what you say--then, according to
you, he who takes ignorance will have a false opinion--am I right?

THEAETETUS:  Yes.

SOCRATES:  He will certainly not think that he has a false opinion?

THEAETETUS:  Of course not.

SOCRATES:  He will think that his opinion is true, and he will fancy that
he knows the things about which he has been deceived?

THEAETETUS:  Certainly.

SOCRATES:  Then he will think that he has captured knowledge and not
ignorance?

THEAETETUS:  Clearly.

SOCRATES:  And thus, after going a long way round, we are once more face to
face with our original difficulty.  The hero of dialectic will retort upon
us:--'O my excellent friends, he will say, laughing, if a man knows the
form of ignorance and the form of knowledge, can he think that one of them
which he knows is the other which he knows? or, if he knows neither of
them, can he think that the one which he knows not is another which he
knows not? or, if he knows one and not the other, can he think the one
which he knows to be the one which he does not know? or the one which he
does not know to be the one which he knows? or will you tell me that there
are other forms of knowledge which distinguish the right and wrong birds,
and which the owner keeps in some other aviaries or graven on waxen blocks
according to your foolish images, and which he may be said to know while he
possesses them, even though he have them not at hand in his mind?  And
thus, in a perpetual circle, you will be compelled to go round and round,
and you will make no progress.'  What are we to say in reply, Theaetetus?

THEAETETUS:  Indeed, Socrates, I do not know what we are to say.

SOCRATES:  Are not his reproaches just, and does not the argument truly
show that we are wrong in seeking for false opinion until we know what
knowledge is; that must be first ascertained; then, the nature of false
opinion?

THEAETETUS:  I cannot but agree with you, Socrates, so far as we have yet
gone.

SOCRATES:  Then, once more, what shall we say that knowledge is?--for we
are not going to lose heart as yet.

THEAETETUS:  Certainly, I shall not lose heart, if you do not.

SOCRATES:  What definition will be most consistent with our former views?

THEAETETUS:  I cannot think of any but our old one, Socrates.

SOCRATES:  What was it?

THEAETETUS:  Knowledge was said by us to be true opinion; and true opinion
is surely unerring, and the results which follow from it are all noble and
good.

SOCRATES:  He who led the way into the river, Theaetetus, said 'The
experiment will show;' and perhaps if we go forward in the search, we may
stumble upon the thing which we are looking for; but if we stay where we
are, nothing will come to light.

THEAETETUS:  Very true; let us go forward and try.

SOCRATES:  The trail soon comes to an end, for a whole profession is
against us.

THEAETETUS:  How is that, and what profession do you mean?

SOCRATES:  The profession of the great wise ones who are called orators and
lawyers; for these persuade men by their art and make them think whatever
they like, but they do not teach them.  Do you imagine that there are any
teachers in the world so clever as to be able to convince others of the
truth about acts of robbery or violence, of which they were not eye-
witnesses, while a little water is flowing in the clepsydra?

THEAETETUS:  Certainly not, they can only persuade them.

SOCRATES:  And would you not say that persuading them is making them have
an opinion?

THEAETETUS:  To be sure.

SOCRATES:  When, therefore, judges are justly persuaded about matters which
you can know only by seeing them, and not in any other way, and when thus
judging of them from report they attain a true opinion about them, they
judge without knowledge, and yet are rightly persuaded, if they have judged
well.

THEAETETUS:  Certainly.

SOCRATES:  And yet, O my friend, if true opinion in law courts and
knowledge are the same, the perfect judge could not have judged rightly
without knowledge; and therefore I must infer that they are not the same.

THEAETETUS:  That is a distinction, Socrates, which I have heard made by
some one else, but I had forgotten it.  He said that true opinion, combined
with reason, was knowledge, but that the opinion which had no reason was
out of the sphere of knowledge; and that things of which there is no
rational account are not knowable--such was the singular expression which
he used--and that things which have a reason or explanation are knowable.

SOCRATES:  Excellent; but then, how did he distinguish between things which
are and are not 'knowable'?  I wish that you would repeat to me what he
said, and then I shall know whether you and I have heard the same tale.

THEAETETUS:  I do not know whether I can recall it; but if another person
would tell me, I think that I could follow him.

SOCRATES:  Let me give you, then, a dream in return for a dream:--Methought
that I too had a dream, and I heard in my dream that the primeval letters
or elements out of which you and I and all other things are compounded,
have no reason or explanation; you can only name them, but no predicate can
be either affirmed or denied of them, for in the one case existence, in the
other non-existence is already implied, neither of which must be added, if
you mean to speak of this or that thing by itself alone.  It should not be
called itself, or that, or each, or alone, or this, or the like; for these
go about everywhere and are applied to all things, but are distinct from
them; whereas, if the first elements could be described, and had a
definition of their own, they would be spoken of apart from all else.  But
none of these primeval elements can be defined; they can only be named, for
they have nothing but a name, and the things which are compounded of them,
as they are complex, are expressed by a combination of names, for the
combination of names is the essence of a definition.  Thus, then, the
elements or letters are only objects of perception, and cannot be defined
or known; but the syllables or combinations of them are known and
expressed, and are apprehended by true opinion.  When, therefore, any one
forms the true opinion of anything without rational explanation, you may
say that his mind is truly exercised, but has no knowledge; for he who
cannot give and receive a reason for a thing, has no knowledge of that
thing; but when he adds rational explanation, then, he is perfected in
knowledge and may be all that I have been denying of him.  Was that the
form in which the dream appeared to you?

THEAETETUS:  Precisely.

SOCRATES:  And you allow and maintain that true opinion, combined with
definition or rational explanation, is knowledge?

THEAETETUS:  Exactly.

SOCRATES:  Then may we assume, Theaetetus, that to-day, and in this casual
manner, we have found a truth which in former times many wise men have
grown old and have not found?

THEAETETUS:  At any rate, Socrates, I am satisfied with the present
statement.

SOCRATES:  Which is probably correct--for how can there be knowledge apart
from definition and true opinion?  And yet there is one point in what has
been said which does not quite satisfy me.

THEAETETUS:  What was it?

SOCRATES:  What might seem to be the most ingenious notion of all:--That
the elements or letters are unknown, but the combination or syllables
known.

THEAETETUS:  And was that wrong?

SOCRATES:  We shall soon know; for we have as hostages the instances which
the author of the argument himself used.

THEAETETUS:  What hostages?

SOCRATES:  The letters, which are the clements; and the syllables, which
are the combinations;--he reasoned, did he not, from the letters of the
alphabet?

THEAETETUS:  Yes; he did.

SOCRATES:  Let us take them and put them to the test, or rather, test
ourselves:--What was the way in which we learned letters? and, first of
all, are we right in saying that syllables have a definition, but that
letters have no definition?

THEAETETUS:  I think so.

SOCRATES:  I think so too; for, suppose that some one asks you to spell the
first syllable of my name:--Theaetetus, he says, what is SO?

THEAETETUS:  I should reply S and O.

SOCRATES:  That is the definition which you would give of the syllable?

THEAETETUS:  I should.

SOCRATES:  I wish that you would give me a similar definition of the S.

THEAETETUS:  But how can any one, Socrates, tell the elements of an
element?  I can only reply, that S is a consonant, a mere noise, as of the
tongue hissing; B, and most other letters, again, are neither vowel-sounds
nor noises.  Thus letters may be most truly said to be undefined; for even
the most distinct of them, which are the seven vowels, have a sound only,
but no definition at all.

SOCRATES:  Then, I suppose, my friend, that we have been so far right in
our idea about knowledge?

THEAETETUS:  Yes; I think that we have.

SOCRATES:  Well, but have we been right in maintaining that the syllables
can be known, but not the letters?

THEAETETUS:  I think so.

SOCRATES:  And do we mean by a syllable two letters, or if there are more,
all of them, or a single idea which arises out of the combination of them?

THEAETETUS:  I should say that we mean all the letters.

SOCRATES:  Take the case of the two letters S and O, which form the first
syllable of my own name; must not he who knows the syllable, know both of
them?

THEAETETUS:  Certainly.

SOCRATES:  He knows, that is, the S and O?

THEAETETUS:  Yes.

SOCRATES:  But can he be ignorant of either singly and yet know both
together?

THEAETETUS:  Such a supposition, Socrates, is monstrous and unmeaning.

SOCRATES:  But if he cannot know both without knowing each, then if he is
ever to know the syllable, he must know the letters first; and thus the
fine theory has again taken wings and departed.

THEAETETUS:  Yes, with wonderful celerity.

SOCRATES:  Yes, we did not keep watch properly.  Perhaps we ought to have
maintained that a syllable is not the letters, but rather one single idea
framed out of them, having a separate form distinct from them.

THEAETETUS:  Very true; and a more likely notion than the other.

SOCRATES:  Take care; let us not be cowards and betray a great and imposing
theory.

THEAETETUS:  No, indeed.

SOCRATES:  Let us assume then, as we now say, that the syllable is a simple
form arising out of the several combinations of harmonious elements--of
letters or of any other elements.

THEAETETUS:  Very good.

SOCRATES:  And it must have no parts.

THEAETETUS:  Why?

SOCRATES:  Because that which has parts must be a whole of all the parts. 
Or would you say that a whole, although formed out of the parts, is a
single notion different from all the parts?

THEAETETUS:  I should.

SOCRATES:  And would you say that all and the whole are the same, or
different?

THEAETETUS:  I am not certain; but, as you like me to answer at once, I
shall hazard the reply, that they are different.

SOCRATES:  I approve of your readiness, Theaetetus, but I must take time to
think whether I equally approve of your answer.

THEAETETUS:  Yes; the answer is the point.

SOCRATES:  According to this new view, the whole is supposed to differ from
all?

THEAETETUS:  Yes.

SOCRATES:  Well, but is there any difference between all (in the plural)
and the all (in the singular)?  Take the case of number:--When we say one,
two, three, four, five, six; or when we say twice three, or three times
two, or four and two, or three and two and one, are we speaking of the same
or of different numbers?

THEAETETUS:  Of the same.

SOCRATES:  That is of six?

THEAETETUS:  Yes.

SOCRATES:  And in each form of expression we spoke of all the six?

THEAETETUS:  True.

SOCRATES:  Again, in speaking of all (in the plural) is there not one thing
which we express?

THEAETETUS:  Of course there is.

SOCRATES:  And that is six?

THEAETETUS:  Yes.

SOCRATES:  Then in predicating the word 'all' of things measured by number,
we predicate at the same time a singular and a plural?

THEAETETUS:  Clearly we do.

SOCRATES:  Again, the number of the acre and the acre are the same; are
they not?

THEAETETUS:  Yes.

SOCRATES:  And the number of the stadium in like manner is the stadium?

THEAETETUS:  Yes.

SOCRATES:  And the army is the number of the army; and in all similar
cases, the entire number of anything is the entire thing?

THEAETETUS:  True.

SOCRATES:  And the number of each is the parts of each?

THEAETETUS:  Exactly.

SOCRATES:  Then as many things as have parts are made up of parts?

THEAETETUS:  Clearly.

SOCRATES:  But all the parts are admitted to be the all, if the entire
number is the all?

THEAETETUS:  True.

SOCRATES:  Then the whole is not made up of parts, for it would be the all,
if consisting of all the parts?

THEAETETUS:  That is the inference.

SOCRATES:  But is a part a part of anything but the whole?

THEAETETUS:  Yes, of the all.

SOCRATES:  You make a valiant defence, Theaetetus.  And yet is not the all
that of which nothing is wanting?

THEAETETUS:  Certainly.

SOCRATES:  And is not a whole likewise that from which nothing is absent?
but that from which anything is absent is neither a whole nor all;--if
wanting in anything, both equally lose their entirety of nature.

THEAETETUS:  I now think that there is no difference between a whole and
all.

SOCRATES:  But were we not saying that when a thing has parts, all the
parts will be a whole and all?

THEAETETUS:  Certainly.

SOCRATES:  Then, as I was saying before, must not the alternative be that
either the syllable is not the letters, and then the letters are not parts
of the syllable, or that the syllable will be the same with the letters,
and will therefore be equally known with them?

THEAETETUS:  You are right.

SOCRATES:  And, in order to avoid this, we suppose it to be different from
them?

THEAETETUS:  Yes.

SOCRATES:  But if letters are not parts of syllables, can you tell me of
any other parts of syllables, which are not letters?

THEAETETUS:  No, indeed, Socrates; for if I admit the existence of parts in
a syllable, it would be ridiculous in me to give up letters and seek for
other parts.

SOCRATES:  Quite true, Theaetetus, and therefore, according to our present
view, a syllable must surely be some indivisible form?

THEAETETUS:  True.

SOCRATES:  But do you remember, my friend, that only a little while ago we
admitted and approved the statement, that of the first elements out of
which all other things are compounded there could be no definition, because
each of them when taken by itself is uncompounded; nor can one rightly
attribute to them the words 'being' or 'this,' because they are alien and
inappropriate words, and for this reason the letters or elements were
indefinable and unknown?

THEAETETUS:  I remember.

SOCRATES:  And is not this also the reason why they are simple and
indivisible?  I can see no other.

THEAETETUS:  No other reason can be given.

SOCRATES:  Then is not the syllable in the same case as the elements or
letters, if it has no parts and is one form?

THEAETETUS:  To be sure.

SOCRATES:  If, then, a syllable is a whole, and has many parts or letters,
the letters as well as the syllable must be intelligible and expressible,
since all the parts are acknowledged to be the same as the whole?

THEAETETUS:  True.

SOCRATES:  But if it be one and indivisible, then the syllables and the
letters are alike undefined and unknown, and for the same reason?

THEAETETUS:  I cannot deny that.

SOCRATES:  We cannot, therefore, agree in the opinion of him who says that
the syllable can be known and expressed, but not the letters.

THEAETETUS:  Certainly not; if we may trust the argument.

SOCRATES:  Well, but will you not be equally inclined to disagree with him,
when you remember your own experience in learning to read?

THEAETETUS:  What experience?

SOCRATES:  Why, that in learning you were kept trying to distinguish the
separate letters both by the eye and by the ear, in order that, when you
heard them spoken or saw them written, you might not be confused by their
position.

THEAETETUS:  Very true.

SOCRATES:  And is the education of the harp-player complete unless he can
tell what string answers to a particular note; the notes, as every one
would allow, are the elements or letters of music?

THEAETETUS:  Exactly.

SOCRATES:  Then, if we argue from the letters and syllables which we know
to other simples and compounds, we shall say that the letters or simple
elements as a class are much more certainly known than the syllables, and
much more indispensable to a perfect knowledge of any subject; and if some
one says that the syllable is known and the letter unknown, we shall
consider that either intentionally or unintentionally he is talking
nonsense?

THEAETETUS:  Exactly.

SOCRATES:  And there might be given other proofs of this belief, if I am
not mistaken.  But do not let us in looking for them lose sight of the
question before us, which is the meaning of the statement, that right
opinion with rational definition or explanation is the most perfect form of
knowledge.

THEAETETUS:  We must not.

SOCRATES:  Well, and what is the meaning of the term 'explanation'?  I
think that we have a choice of three meanings.

THEAETETUS:  What are they?

SOCRATES:  In the first place, the meaning may be, manifesting one's
thought by the voice with verbs and nouns, imaging an opinion in the stream
which flows from the lips, as in a mirror or water.  Does not explanation
appear to be of this nature?

THEAETETUS:  Certainly; he who so manifests his thought, is said to explain
himself.

SOCRATES:  And every one who is not born deaf or dumb is able sooner or
later to manifest what he thinks of anything; and if so, all those who have
a right opinion about anything will also have right explanation; nor will
right opinion be anywhere found to exist apart from knowledge.

THEAETETUS:  True.

SOCRATES:  Let us not, therefore, hastily charge him who gave this account
of knowledge with uttering an unmeaning word; for perhaps he only intended
to say, that when a person was asked what was the nature of anything, he
should be able to answer his questioner by giving the elements of the
thing.

THEAETETUS:  As for example, Socrates...?

SOCRATES:  As, for example, when Hesiod says that a waggon is made up of a
hundred planks.  Now, neither you nor I could describe all of them
individually; but if any one asked what is a waggon, we should be content
to answer, that a waggon consists of wheels, axle, body, rims, yoke.

THEAETETUS:  Certainly.

SOCRATES:  And our opponent will probably laugh at us, just as he would if
we professed to be grammarians and to give a grammatical account of the
name of Theaetetus, and yet could only tell the syllables and not the
letters of your name--that would be true opinion, and not knowledge; for
knowledge, as has been already remarked, is not attained until, combined
with true opinion, there is an enumeration of the elements out of which
anything is composed.

THEAETETUS:  Yes.

SOCRATES:  In the same general way, we might also have true opinion about a
waggon; but he who can describe its essence by an enumeration of the
hundred planks, adds rational explanation to true opinion, and instead of
opinion has art and knowledge of the nature of a waggon, in that he attains
to the whole through the elements.

THEAETETUS:  And do you not agree in that view, Socrates?

SOCRATES:  If you do, my friend; but I want to know first, whether you
admit the resolution of all things into their elements to be a rational
explanation of them, and the consideration of them in syllables or larger
combinations of them to be irrational--is this your view?

THEAETETUS:  Precisely.

SOCRATES:  Well, and do you conceive that a man has knowledge of any
element who at one time affirms and at another time denies that element of
something, or thinks that the same thing is composed of different elements
at different times?

THEAETETUS:  Assuredly not.

SOCRATES:  And do you not remember that in your case and in that of others
this often occurred in the process of learning to read?

THEAETETUS:  You mean that I mistook the letters and misspelt the
syllables?

SOCRATES:  Yes.

THEAETETUS:  To be sure; I perfectly remember, and I am very far from
supposing that they who are in this condition have knowledge.

SOCRATES:  When a person at the time of learning writes the name of
Theaetetus, and thinks that he ought to write and does write Th and e; but,
again, meaning to write the name of Theododorus, thinks that he ought to
write and does write T and e--can we suppose that he knows the first
syllables of your two names?

THEAETETUS:  We have already admitted that such a one has not yet attained
knowledge.

SOCRATES:  And in like manner be may enumerate without knowing them the
second and third and fourth syllables of your name?

THEAETETUS:  He may.

SOCRATES:  And in that case, when he knows the order of the letters and can
write them out correctly, he has right opinion?

THEAETETUS:  Clearly.

SOCRATES:  But although we admit that he has right opinion, he will still
be without knowledge?

THEAETETUS:  Yes.

SOCRATES:  And yet he will have explanation, as well as right opinion, for
he knew the order of the letters when he wrote; and this we admit to be
explanation.

THEAETETUS:  True.

SOCRATES:  Then, my friend, there is such a thing as right opinion united
with definition or explanation, which does not as yet attain to the
exactness of knowledge.

THEAETETUS:  It would seem so.

SOCRATES:  And what we fancied to be a perfect definition of knowledge is a
dream only.  But perhaps we had better not say so as yet, for were there
not three explanations of knowledge, one of which must, as we said, be
adopted by him who maintains knowledge to be true opinion combined with
rational explanation?  And very likely there may be found some one who will
not prefer this but the third.

THEAETETUS:  You are quite right; there is still one remaining.  The first
was the image or expression of the mind in speech; the second, which has
just been mentioned, is a way of reaching the whole by an enumeration of
the elements.  But what is the third definition?

SOCRATES:  There is, further, the popular notion of telling the mark or
sign of difference which distinguishes the thing in question from all
others.

THEAETETUS:  Can you give me any example of such a definition?

SOCRATES:  As, for example, in the case of the sun, I think that you would
be contented with the statement that the sun is the brightest of the
heavenly bodies which revolve about the earth.

THEAETETUS:  Certainly.

SOCRATES:  Understand why:--the reason is, as I was just now saying, that
if you get at the difference and distinguishing characteristic of each
thing, then, as many persons affirm, you will get at the definition or
explanation of it; but while you lay hold only of the common and not of the
characteristic notion, you will only have the definition of those things to
which this common quality belongs.

THEAETETUS:  I understand you, and your account of definition is in my
judgment correct.

SOCRATES:  But he, who having right opinion about anything, can find out
the difference which distinguishes it from other things will know that of
which before he had only an opinion.

THEAETETUS:  Yes; that is what we are maintaining.

SOCRATES:  Nevertheless, Theaetetus, on a nearer view, I find myself quite
disappointed; the picture, which at a distance was not so bad, has now
become altogether unintelligible.

THEAETETUS:  What do you mean?

SOCRATES:  I will endeavour to explain:  I will suppose myself to have true
opinion of you, and if to this I add your definition, then I have
knowledge, but if not, opinion only.

THEAETETUS:  Yes.

SOCRATES:  The definition was assumed to be the interpretation of your
difference.

THEAETETUS:  True.

SOCRATES:  But when I had only opinion, I had no conception of your
distinguishing characteristics.

THEAETETUS:  I suppose not.

SOCRATES:  Then I must have conceived of some general or common nature
which no more belonged to you than to another.

THEAETETUS:  True.

SOCRATES:  Tell me, now--How in that case could I have formed a judgment of
you any more than of any one else?  Suppose that I imagine Theaetetus to be
a man who has nose, eyes, and mouth, and every other member complete; how
would that enable me to distinguish Theaetetus from Theodorus, or from some
outer barbarian?

THEAETETUS:  How could it?

SOCRATES:  Or if I had further conceived of you, not only as having nose
and eyes, but as having a snub nose and prominent eyes, should I have any
more notion of you than of myself and others who resemble me?

THEAETETUS:  Certainly not.

SOCRATES:  Surely I can have no conception of Theaetetus until your snub-
nosedness has left an impression on my mind different from the snub-
nosedness of all others whom I have ever seen, and until your other
peculiarities have a like distinctness; and so when I meet you to-morrow
the right opinion will be re-called?

THEAETETUS:  Most true.

SOCRATES:  Then right opinion implies the perception of differences?

THEAETETUS:  Clearly.

SOCRATES:  What, then, shall we say of adding reason or explanation to
right opinion?  If the meaning is, that we should form an opinion of the
way in which something differs from another thing, the proposal is
ridiculous.

THEAETETUS:  How so?

SOCRATES:  We are supposed to acquire a right opinion of the differences
which distinguish one thing from another when we have already a right
opinion of them, and so we go round and round:--the revolution of the
scytal, or pestle, or any other rotatory machine, in the same circles, is
as nothing compared with such a requirement; and we may be truly described
as the blind directing the blind; for to add those things which we already
have, in order that we may learn what we already think, is like a soul
utterly benighted.

THEAETETUS:  Tell me; what were you going to say just now, when you asked
the question?

SOCRATES:  If, my boy, the argument, in speaking of adding the definition,
had used the word to 'know,' and not merely 'have an opinion' of the
difference, this which is the most promising of all the definitions of
knowledge would have come to a pretty end, for to know is surely to acquire
knowledge.

THEAETETUS:  True.

SOCRATES:  And so, when the question is asked, What is knowledge? this fair
argument will answer 'Right opinion with knowledge,'--knowledge, that is,
of difference, for this, as the said argument maintains, is adding the
definition.

THEAETETUS:  That seems to be true.

SOCRATES:  But how utterly foolish, when we are asking what is knowledge,
that the reply should only be, right opinion with knowledge of difference
or of anything!  And so, Theaetetus, knowledge is neither sensation nor
true opinion, nor yet definition and explanation accompanying and added to
true opinion?

THEAETETUS:  I suppose not.

SOCRATES:  And are you still in labour and travail, my dear friend, or have
you brought all that you have to say about knowledge to the birth?

THEAETETUS:  I am sure, Socrates, that you have elicited from me a good
deal more than ever was in me.

SOCRATES:  And does not my art show that you have brought forth wind, and
that the offspring of your brain are not worth bringing up?

THEAETETUS:  Very true.

SOCRATES:  But if, Theaetetus, you should ever conceive afresh, you will be
all the better for the present investigation, and if not, you will be
soberer and humbler and gentler to other men, and will be too modest to
fancy that you know what you do not know.  These are the limits of my art;
I can no further go, nor do I know aught of the things which great and
famous men know or have known in this or former ages.  The office of a
midwife I, like my mother, have received from God; she delivered women, I
deliver men; but they must be young and noble and fair.

And now I have to go to the porch of the King Archon, where I am to meet
Meletus and his indictment.  To-morrow morning, Theodorus, I shall hope to
see you again at this place.





End of Etext of Theaetetus, by Plato

Return to www.BrainFly.Net